The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 0 [1997]

Mrs. Dorris Jenkins, who taught history, said that she had two ambitions in life. One was to be in a footnote. That had already happened, since a former student had put her in a footnote to his dissertation. The other was to have a student become a philosopher. Although at the time I was still thinking that I wanted to go into archaeology, I had started studying philosophy, so I asked her exactly what it would take for her to consider that a student had become a philosopher. She was uncompromising: The criterion was a Ph.D. in Philosophy.

My last semester in high school, Mrs. Jenkins organized a debate team, which I joined. But she died suddenly that very term. I didn't go into philosophy because of that, but it did seem like a very serious portent. There would be no other students after me who might become philosophers. And that, as it happened, is what I did. The following dissertation is finally how I got the Ph.D., and there did not seem to be a more appropriate dedication than to the teacher whose final ambition was thus fulfilled.

In Memoriam

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 1

C.G. Jung (1875-1961), "The Transcendent Function," in The Structure and Dynamics of the Psyche, Vol. 8 Collected Works, Bollingen Series XX, Princeton University Press, 1972, pp. 69-91.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 2

Immanuel Kant (1724-1804), "Of the right of pure reason to an extension in its practical use which is not possible to it in its speculative use," Critique of Practical Reason, The Library of the Liberal Arts, Bobs-Merrill, New York, 1956, pp. 52-59.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 3

Ibid. p. 166.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 4

Kant, "The autonomy of the will as the supreme principle of morality," Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, Library of the Liberal Arts, Bobs-Merrill, New York, 1959, p. 59.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 5

Kant, "Of the division of philosophy" etc., Critique of Judgment, Hafner Library of Classics, New York, 1951, pp. 7-15.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 6

Jakob Fries (1773-1843). While Shlomo Avineri's (Hegel's Theory of the Modern State, Cambridge University Press, 1972, pp. 119-122) exposure of Fries's anti-semitism is disturbing, the conclusions he draws from it are unwarranted. An accusation of "subjectivism" both against Kant and Fries is baseless -- a distortion in the defense of Hegel that is especially unfair because of the likely unfamiliarity of readers with Fries's thought. The equation of either Fries or the Burschenschaften with the Nazis is a gross anachronism. The fact of the age of Prussian and Austrian reactionary oppression and authoritarianism, beside which anyone expressing nationalistic and republican sentiments automatically qualifies as a liberal of the time. The verdict of history is evident in the fact that the black, red, and gold flag of the students and their movement became an abiding symbol, at first of nationalism, but later entirely of liberalism and republicanism -- a symbol that surfaced both in 1848 and in the Weimar Republic. The conservatism championed by Hegel is what in fact led to the co-option of nationalism by the authoritarian state that in truth made the Nazi terror possible. There is no thought here of excusing Fries; but in the perspective of history we should see that the students need not have been pure and enlightened to have been more progressive than the German governments. If there had been a revolution in 1817, it is likely there would [have been] a Terror as in similar revolutions. Germany, spared such horrors, benefited from gradual change only by moving steadily to autocracy, dictatorship, and catastrophe. Whatever Fries's prejudices or role may have been earlier, by the time the Nazis came, the representatives of his tradition were as firmly opposed to Hitler as they could possibly have been. So we should not simply dismiss Fries for this reprehensible failing: few dismiss Marx for his anti-semitic remarks and Heidegger, although a publicly proclaimed Nazi sympathizer, is none the less a philosopher to be taken seriously. If historians of science now can blind themselves to the participation in the Third Reich of Werner Heisenberg -- even to the point of attempting to develop quantum Uncertainty into a moral principle -- then we can at least grant to Fries an examination of the principles of his philosophy. Harald Höffding's judgment of Fries was this:

Scorned by Hegel, and still scoffed at by those who entertain a romantic admiration for Romantic philosophy, this sober inquirer has nevertheless in his theory of knowledge, as well as in his psychology and ethics, developed thoughts which have always maintained their validity and their value, while the speculative systems have long ceased to possess any but historical interest. [A History of Modern Philosophy, Vo. 2, Dover, New York, 1955, page 248.]

So sympathetic a tribute must have come from an estimation of Fries's strengths, not from a polemical exposure of his weaknesses.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 7

Leonard Nelson (1882-1927). The Vorlesungen über die Grundlagen der Ethik in three volumes, Kritik der praktischen Vernunft, System der philosophischen Ethik und Pädagogik, and System der philosophischen Rechtslehre und Politik. These are volumes IV, V, and VI of the Gesammelte Schriften, Felix Meiner Verlag, Hamburg, 1972. Only the System of Ethics (Yale, 1956) has been published in English, although a photocopied manuscript translation of the Critique (1957) was made available by the Leonard Nelson Foundation in 1970.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 8

Nelson, "The Critical Method and the Relation of Psychology to Philosophy," Socratic Method and Critical Philosophy, Dover, New York, 1965, pp. 105-157.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 9

Robert Paul Wolff, "The Subjective Deduction," Kant's Theory of Mental Activity, Harvard, 1963, pp. 100-164, Immanuel Kant, "The A Priori Grounds of the Possibility of Experience," Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Norman Kemp Smith, St. Martin's Press, New York, 1965, pp. 129-140.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 10

Nelson, op. cit., "The Impossibility of the 'Theory of Knowledge'," pp. 185-205, and p. 118.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 11

Ibid. pp. 121-123.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 12

Wolff, op. cit., p. 109.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 13

C.G. Jung, Psychological Types, Bollingen Paperbacks, Princeton, 1976, pp. 2-4.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 14

Nelson, op. cit., p. 75
Rudolf Otto (1869-1937), The Idea of the Holy, Oxford, 1972, pp. 145-147.
Nelson, System of Ethics, Yale, 1956, p. 15.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 15

Nelson, Socratic Method etc., p. 153. cf. note 10.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 16

Kant, Pure Reason, p. 65.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 17

Nelson, op. cit., p. 120.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 18

Ibid., p. 117.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 19

Alan R. White, "The Correspondence Theory" & "The Coherence Theory," Truth, Anchor, New York, 1970, pp. 102-122.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 20

Nelson, op. cit., "Prejudice of Logical Dogmatism," p. 141 and diagram p. 146.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 21

Ibid. pp. 141-153.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 22

Ibid. p. 123.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 23

Ibid., "The Regressive Method: Induction and Abstraction," pp. 105-110.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 24

Ibid., "The Verification of Judgments: Proof, Demonstration, and Deduction," pp. 111-121.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 25

Kant, op. cit., p. 120.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 26

Nelson, op. cit., "Theory of Deduction," pp. 122-125.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 27

Ibid. p. 126.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 28

Aristotle, Topica, Loeb Classical Library, Harvard, 1966, pp. 272-273 -- ho dialektiòs syllogismós.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 29

Nelson, "Philosophy and Axiomatics," op. cit., pp. 164-167. The term "metalanguage" is not used here; but the meaning is clear, and Hilbert's use of the term "metamathematics is cited.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 30

Ibid., "The Prejudice of the Transcendental," pp. 134-135.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 31

Franz Brentano, Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint, Routledge & Kegan Paul, Humanities Press, New York, 1973, p. 88.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 32

Edmund Husserl, Cartesian Meditations, Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, 1970, p. 41.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 33

Michael Gelven, A Commentary on Heidegger's "Being and Time", Harper Torchbooks, New York, 1970, p. 18. J.L. Mehta, The Philosophy of Martin Heidegger, Harper Torchbooks, New York, 1971. Page 39:

...and aims at showing how the Nothing, as the other to all that is, constitutes Dasein's transcendence as experienced in the first instance when we seek to ascend from beings (essents) to Being.

This is one point of origin for the concept of negative transcendence.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 34

Sigmund Freud, The Ego and the Id, The Norton Library, New York, 1962, p. 5.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 35

Arthur Schopenhauer (1788-1860), The World as Will and Representation, Volume 1, Dover, New York, 1966, p. 112.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 36

G.S. Kirk & J.E. Raven, The Presocratic Philosophers, Cambridge, 1964, p. 405 -- the manner in which the void answered Eleaticism.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 37

Kant, op. cit., "Transcendental Illusion," pp. 298-299.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 38

Mehta, op. cit., "Truth of Being," pp. 205-223.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 39

Francis M. Cornford, Plato's Theory of Knowledge, Library of the Liberal Arts, Bobbs-Merrill, New York, 1957, pp. 89-92.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 40

C.L. Baker, Introduction to Generative-Transformational Syntax, Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey, 1978, pp. 14-25.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 41

G.E. Moore, Principia Ethica, Cambridge, 1971, p. 146.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 42

Kant, Practical Reason, pp. 85-86.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 43

R.C. Zaehner, The Teachings of the Magi, Oxford, 1976, p. 18.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 44

Otto, op. cit., pp. 6-7.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 45

Wolff, op. cit., pp. 31 & 25, respectively.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 46

Schopenhauer, op. cit., p. 433.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 47

Kant, Pure Reason, pp. 105-106.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 48

William James, The Principles of Psychology, Volume 1, Dover, New York, 1950, pp. 249-258.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 49

Raymond J. McCall, Basic Logic, Barnes & Noble, New York, 1967, pp.1-7.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 50

Baker, op. cit., p. 59. The terminology may obscure the meaning here. Phrase structure rules provide the elements of the sentence and then transformational rules essentially shuffle them around.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 51

Kant, op. cit., p. 105.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 52

compare D.M. Armstrong, "What is Consciousness?" The Nature of Mind, Cornell, 1981, p. 55: "Consciousness is the cream on the cake of mentality, a special and sophisticated development of mentality."

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 53

Kant, op. cit., pp. 182-183; and Wolff, op. cit., pp. 211-213. And Kant p. 135.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 54

Panayot Butchvarov, Being Qua Being, Indian University Press, Bloomington, 1979, p. 21.

Jon Barwise and John Perry, Situations and Attitudes, MIT Press, 1983, p. 4.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 55

McCall, op. cit., pp. 16-17.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 56

Jacques Maritain, Formal Logic, Sheed & Ward, New York (no date), p. 225. A Thomist, Maritain rises to the defense of Aristotelian quantification.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 57

Kant, op. cit., p. 92.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 58

Sanskrit vid, from which véda, "knowledge," e.g. the sacred Vedas. Arthur MacDonell, A Practical Sanskrit Dictionary, Oxford, 1971, pp. 282 & 298. In Greek (w)id is a strong root, with Aplaut grades in 0, e, and o. The present form *eídô is not used; but both eîdon and oîda are principle parts of the verb hóraô, "see," with a secondary meaning for oîda, "have seen," as a present tense "to know." Liddell and Scott's Intermediate Greek-English Lexicon, Oxford, 1964, p. 226-227. See page 375 for idéa. The Latin cognate root video is also mentioned. The Old English is witan, from which "wit," "wise," "wisdom," etc., as in any ordinary dictionary providing etymologies.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 59

Baker, op. cit., p. 92.

Noam Chomsky, Aspects of the Theory of Syntax, MIT Press, 1975, p. 136. In linguistic usage "deep structure" is a more relative term, and deep structures can presuppose the phase structure rules of particular languages. The feeling about phase structure rules is almost as though the formal schemas exist first and then "lexical items" are filled in. But that can hardly be the route by which meaning, which from the beginning must involve the content of lexical items, is transformed into a linguistic expression. A semantic representation is at least the conception of pure meaning.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 60

Baker, op. cit., 220-226.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 61

Bruce Biggs, "Parts of Speech: The Base Classes," Let's Learn Maori, A.H. & A.W. Reed, Auckland, New Zealand, 1969, pp. 50-53. Adjectives come out as "statives," i.e. stative verbs.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 62

Sir Alan Gardiner, Egyptian Grammar, Oxford, 1964, pp. 234 & 326. The former speaks of the "sole surviving relic ... of the Semitic finite verb."

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 63

Ibid. p. 431. The phonology of the Coptic verb classes -- for tenses, etc., any Coptic grammar.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 64

Barwise and Perry, op. cit., pp. xi-xii.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 65

Because they are only "forms of sensibility." Kant, op. cit., p. 90 -- a backhanded statement that "this mode of intuiting in space and time need not be limited to human sensibility," although it may be.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 66

Grete Henry, "The Significance of Behaviour Study for the Critique of Reason," Ratio, Volume XV No. 2, Basil Blackwell, December 1973, pp. 208-209. Here one of Nelson's students abandons the notion of "immediate knowledge."

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 67

Schopenhauer. op. cit. p. 352. One of the finest images in all of philosophy.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 68

Kant, op. cit., pp. 143-144.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 69

Ibid. pp. 152-153. Kant's Second Edition statement of the thought noted in 68.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 70

Ibid. p. 111.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 71

Wolff, op. cit., pp. 121-125

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 72

Kant, op. cit., p. 112

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 73

Ibid., pp. 143-144. Here Kant continues, first saying that "apprehension" is when the action of synthesis is "immediately directed upon perceptions," and then turning right around and saying that imagination must have "previously" taken up impressions in order to have formed an image. This reflects Kant's change of mind; for on page 124 he has just said: "But since intuition stands in no need whatsoever of the functions of thought, appearances would none the less present objects to our intuition."

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 74

Ibid., pp. 89-90.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 75

Ibid., p. 134.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 76

Ibid., p. 25 note.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 77

D.M. Armstrong, Belief, Truth and Knowledge, Cambridge, 1974. Although I will be critical of Armstrong, his chapter "The Infinite Regress of Reasons," pp. 150161, is a very excellent treatment -- qualified only by the rejection here of the thesis that knowledge entails belief.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 78

Kant, op. cit., pp. 345-350.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 79

Ibid., p. 27.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 80

Schopenhauer, op. cit., p. 444, & for sub/obj. p. 13.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 81

Armstrong, op. cit., pp. 182-183.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 82

Roderick M. Chisholm, Theory of Knowledge, Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey, pp. 5-6. That belief should be considered part of all mediate knowledge is unobjectionable; the difficulties come precisely with "non-inferential" beliefs, which both demand the certainty of immediate knowledge yet suffer from all the uncertainties and possible arbitrariness of propositional formulations.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 83

Armstrong, op. cit., pp. 157-158.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 84

Ibid., pp. 191-192.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 85

Ibid., p. 156.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 86

Ibid., p. 157.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 87

The original conception of the "regress of reasons" is due to Aristotle: Posterior Analytics, Loeb Classical Library, Harvard, 1966, pp. 33 & 261 -- where the regress ends in first principles known by noûs.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 88

Cornford, op. cit., pp. 140-163, where knowledge as true belief and knowledge as true belief with an account are both rejected in the Theaetetus.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 89

Wolff, op. cit., 229-230.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 90

Kant, op. cit., pp. 134-135.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 91

Ibid., p. 126.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 92

Wolff, op. cit., p. 15.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 93

Ibid., pp. 278-279 -- Wolff's final formulation for Kant's proof of causality.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 94

Schopenhauer, op. cit., p. 8: "Succession is the form of the principle of sufficient reason in time, and succession is the whole essence and nature of time." Since Kant's argument in the Analogies of Experience is based on time consciousness, succession exhausts the matter for Schopenhauer. Cf. p. 473.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 95

Wolff, op. cit., p. 3.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 96

Nothing that is said about synthesis in the Analytic would require that it be Euclidean or otherwise. For his sense of the structure of space, Kant certainly relies on the structure of space as a form of sensibility, which is peculiar to the Aesthetic. The argument then is just whether we do or do not see space as Euclidean, and that is nothing to belabor Kant with.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 97

Wolff, op. cit., p. 208 -- on the Schematism's introduction of the "modes of time-consciousness."

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 98

Ibid., p. 219.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 99

Frederic M. Wheelock, Latin, Barnes & Noble, New York, 1966, p. 123 for declension of comparatives, p. 86 for case taken by â, "from."

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 100

Aristotle, On Interpretation, Loeb Classical Library, Harvard, 1962, pp. 131-141.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 101

Alston H. Chase and Henry Phillips, A New Introduction to Greek, Harvard, 1965, p. 113.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 102

A. Meillett, Introduction à L'Étude Comparative des Langues Indo-Européennes, Alabama, 1967, p. 204.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 103

In the Greek Indicative, both the imperfect and aorist have past significance. Just as English does not avail itself much of the form of the present aorist to express a present aorist, the only sense of the Greek present seems to be imperfect, just as in the Subjunctive the present is truly an imperfect.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 104

Wolff, op. cit., p. 244.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 105

see note 87.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 106

Nelson, Progress and Regress in Philosophy, Vol. 1, Basil Blackwell, Oxford, 1970, p. 105. The little known work of Kant mentioned here, Enquiry -- into the Clarity of the Principles of Natural Theology and Morality, is suitably symbolic of what the Friesians grasped in Kant while others did not. Kant's considerations suit the distinction between intuitive and non-intuitive knowledge as well as they do his own later theories.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 107

Plato, Timaeus, Penguin, Baltimore, 1965, p. 70.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 108

Nelson, Socratic Method etc., pp. 190-191 -- Nelson's attack on the "mediacy of all knowledge."

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 109

Ibid. 191.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 110

Kirk and Raven, op. cit., p. 405.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 111

William Wallace, The Logic of Hegel, Oxford, 1972, p. 161. "The Absolute is the Nought."

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 112

Cassell's New Latin Dictionary, Funk & Wagnalls, New York, 1960, p. 360 (maneo), p. 610 (transcendo).

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 113

Jean-Paul Sartre, The Transcendence of the Ego, Noonday Press, New York, 1971. p. 42. "Translucence."

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 114

Schopenhauer, op. cit., p. 5.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 115

Kant, op. cit., p. 146.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 116

H. and H.A. Frankfort, Before Philosophy, Penguin, Baltimore, 1963, p. 30.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 117

Kirk and Raven, op. cit., pp. 299-300.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 118

T.J. De Boer, The History of Philosophy in Islam, Dover, New York, 1967, pp. 57-62 -- "Atomistic Kalam" -- the most interesting aspect of philosophy in Islam is that the most interesting doctrines, like this, like Occasionalism, like al-Ghazzâlî's critique of causality, were originated by theologians who not only did not call themselves "philosophers" (falâsifah) but were hostile to those who did.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 119

Wolff, op. cit., p. 10.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 120

Schopenhauer, op. cit., p. 10.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 121

Majid Fakhry, Islamic Occasionalism, Allen & Unwin, London, 1958, pp. 56-82 -- "The Repudiation of Causality by al-Ghazâlî."

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 122

Kant, Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, pp. 29-31.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 123

Plato, op. cit., p. 41.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 124

Schopenhauer, op. cit., p. 100.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 125

Armstrong, The Nature of Mind, pp. 27-31 -- "The Problem of the Secondary Qualities."

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 126

Alfred North Whitehead, Science and the Modern World, Free Press, New York, 1967, p. 91.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 127

Nelson, "Pleasure," Critique of Practical Reason, pp. 324-332.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 128

Schopenhauer, op. cit., p. 130.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 129

Ibid., p. 40.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 130

Ibid., p.5. cf. Br[.]hadâran[.]yaka Upanis[.]ad, IV Adhyâya, 5 Brâhman[.]a, 15.; The Upanis[.]ads, volume II, translated by F. Max Müller, Dover Publications, New York, 1962, p. 185

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 131

Ibid., pp. 11-13.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 132

Ibid., pp. 19-21.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 133

Ibid., p. 100.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 134

Ibid., p. 170.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 135

Ibid., pp. 194-197.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 136

Ibid., p. 376 -- "in direct contradiction to Kant," although Hume is not mentioned as an alternative.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 137

Ibid., p. 373.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 138

Nelson, Ethics, pp. 112-116.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 139

Jung, Symbols of Transformation, Bollingen XX, Princeton, 1976, p. 158; and The Archetypes and the Collective Unconscious, Princeton, 1975, p. 26.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 140

Jung, Symbols of Transformation, p. 137.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 141

Jung, Archetypes and the Collective Unconscious, pp. 43-44 -- "they are patterns of instinctual behaviour."

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 142

For the influence of Schopenhauer: Jung, Memories, Dreams, Reflections, Vintage, 1973, p. 69.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 143

Jung, Four Archetypes, Mother/Rebirth/Spirit/Trickster, Bollingen, Princeton, 1973.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 144

Jung, Archetypes etc., pp. 29-30.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 145

Schopenhauer, "On Women," Parerga and Paralipomena, Vol. 2, Clarendon, Oxford, 1974, p. 619.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 146

Nelson, Progress and Regress in Philosophy, Vol. w, pp. 233-234.

"Intimation" however, consists in subordinating the objects of knowledge to those of faith and thus represents a third form of conviction, as it can neither claim the self-evidence of knowledge nor even (as faith can) become clear in the logical form of concepts. Yet it is not inferior in its degrees of certainty and in the reliability of its conviction.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 147

Ibid., pp. 229, 230. Nearby (p. 226) is a passage very revealing of my differences with Fries and Nelson:

This insuperable contingency in the givenness of the objects of our knowledge shows very clearly that the existence of the objects of our knowledge is dependent on their being known. For we are compelled by an unavoidable notion of our own pure reason to assume that nothing can be really real unless it is also determined as necessary. On this assumption contingency cannot be a quality of reality, but can only express some defect in our knowledge of reality, namely lack of knowledge of its necessity. So the insuperable contingency of the objects of our knowledge is the clearest proof of the fact that our knowledge is necessarily limited in quality, the fact that we do not know things as-they-really-are.

Here the "unavoidable notion" may be assigned to the sense of numinous pseudo-necessity; but Nelson has not tempered that with the corresponding sense of ur-contingency, which would prevent his Kant-like conclusion that we do not know things as they are in themselves. Here contingency is just as fundamental as necessity; and the various modes of each are complexly interrelated.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 148

Ibid., pp. 227-230.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 149

Nelson, Socratic Method etc., p. xix note -- this is in the introduction of Julius Kraft.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 150

Otto, op. cit., "Mysterium Tremendum," pp. 12-24.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 151

Jung, Archetypes etc., p. 28.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 152

Ibid., p. 7. At the same time Jung acknowledges the most powerful religious sense, as here, "Tribal lore is always sacred and dangerous," and as in note 151, "unconditional, dangerous, taboo, magical."

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 153

Nelson, op. cit., "The Socratic Method," pp. 1-40.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 154

Aristotle, Nichomachean Ethics, Library of the Liberal Arts, Bobbs-Merrill, Indianapolis, 1975, pp. 33-35.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 155

Chomsky, op. cit., pp. 52-53.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 156

Moore, op. cit. pp. 52-53.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 157

Nelson, Ethics, p. 14.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 158

Schopenhauer, The World as Will etc., p. 100.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 159

Kant, Pure Reason, p. 474.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 160

Schopenhauer, op. cit., p. 233.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 161

Jung, The Structure and Dynamics of the Psyche, p. 69.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 162

Nelson, op. cit., pp. 32-35.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 163

Ibid., pp. 185-187, and Critique of Practical Reason, pp. 343-404 -- "Examination of Aesthetic Interest."

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 164

Kant, Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, p. 9.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 165

Zaehner, op. cit., pp. 17-18.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 166

Kant, Practical Reason, p. 86.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 167

Mathews' Chinese-English Dictionary, Harvard, 1972, p. 464. "Jên" in Wade-Giles.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 168

Nelson, Ethics, p. 88.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 169

Kant, Foundations etc., p. 47.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 170

Kant, Practical Reason, pp. 135-136. Earlier, in beginning to deal with the "highest good" (pp. 112-114): "The moral law is the sole determining ground of the pure will." Only perfect goodness, morally, merits perfect happiness and so, by the agency of God, ensures it. Whatever merits happiness, here the moral law is certainly not the "sole determining ground of the pure will."

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 171

Nelson, op. cit., p. 187.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 172

Kant, Judgment, p. 56.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 173

Aristotle, op. cit., pp. 6-19.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 174

Kant Practical Reason, p. 126.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 175

Zaehner, op. cit., pp. 18 & 55.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 176

Jung, Memories etc., p. 326.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 177

Jung, Answer to Job, Bollingen, Princeton, 1973.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 178

Genesis 3:11. Revised Standard Version, Cokesbury, 1952.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 179

Jung, op. cit., p. 13.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 180

Genesis 3:22.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 181

Alan W. Watts, "The Rise and Development of Zen," The Way of Zen, pp. 77-112.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 182

Heidegger, An Introduction to Metaphysics, Doubleday, 1961,p. 139. Adding to the difficulty of Heidegger's meaning is a printing error that transposed "techne" and "dike" on line eleven.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 183

Ibid., p. 166 -- "the inner truth and greatness of this movement..."

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 184

Matthew 5:39. E Kaine Diathike, United Bible Societies, 1967, Biblike Etairia, Athens.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 185

Matthew 5:43-48.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 186

Geoffrey Ashe, Gandhi, pp. 99-105.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 187

De Boer, op. cit., 43-55.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 188

Jung, "Synchronicity: An Acausal Connecting Principle," The Structure and Dynamics of the Psyche, pp. 421-458.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 189

P.T. Raju, The Philosophical Traditions of India, pp. 421-458.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 190

Zaehner, op. cit. p. 140.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 191

Matthew 6:31-33.

Return to text

The Origin of Value in a Transcendent Function, Note 192

Kant, Pure Reason, p. 636.

Return to text

Copyright (c) 1985, 1997 Kelley L. Ross, Ph.D. All Rights Reserved