Morality, Justice,
and Judicial Moralism

The worst edict that can possibly be imagined...An edict that permits liberty of conscience, the worst thing in the world.

Pope Clement VIII on the Edict of Nantes, 1598, by which King Henry IV of France declared that French Protestants, the Huguenots, were (mostly) free to practice their religion. Revoked by King Louis XIV in 1685.


Nous ne pouvons être tenus au-delà de nos forces et de nos moyens. À cette cause, parce que les effets et exécutions ne sont aucunement en notre puissance, et qu'il n'y a rien en bon escient en notre puissance, que la volonté: en celle-là se fondent par nécessité, et s'établissent toutes le règles du devoir de l'homme.

We cannot be held responsible beyond our strength and means, since the resulting events are quite outside of our control and, in fact, we have power over nothing except our will; which is the basis upon which all rules concerning man's duty must of necessity be founded.

Michel de Montaigne, Essays, "That our actions should be judged by our intentions," Book One, Chapter 7 [1580, translated by J.M. Cohen, Penguin, 1958, 1993, p.25], French text, Essais de Michel de Montaigne, Livre premier, édition présentée, établie et annotée, par Emmanuel Naya, Delphine Reguig, et Alexandre Tarrête [Éditions Gallimard, 2009, p.151].


Whenever the offense inspires less horror than the punishment, the rigor of penal law is obliged to give way to the common feelings of mankind.

Edward Gibbon


...and surely it is better for the world that men should be right from wrong motives than that they would do wrong with the best intentions. What concerns society is conduct, not opinion: if only our actions are just and good, it matters not a straw to others whether our opinions are mistaken.

Sir James Frazer, Psyche's Task [1909]


"...and in daily contact with her without feeling a passionate regard for her. Do you blame me, Mr. Holmes?"

"I do not blame you for feeling it. I should blame you if you expressed it, since this young lady was in a sense under your protection."

Sherlock Holmes, "The Problem of Thor Bridge", The Case Book of Sherlock Holmes [Sir Arthur Conan Doyle, 1927]


The crucial role of self-exaltation underlies the way that those with opposing opinions are viewed. It is not sufficient, for example, to depict those who believe in preserving peace through military deterrence as mistaken, factually incorrect, illogical in their analysis, or dangerous in their conclusions. All of those things, even if true, would still leave them on the same moral plane as the anointed visionaries and would leave both subject to the same requirements of evidence and logic, as their arguments are laid before others to decide. What is necessary, from the standpoint of self-exaltation, is to depict proponents of military detererence as not "really" being for peace, as being either bloodthirsty or acting as venal representatives of special interests who desire war for their own ends.

Thomas Sowell, The Quest for Cosmic Justice [The Free Press, 1999, pp. 138-139]


If there were a modern Spanish Inquisition in America today, it wouldn't be Bob Jones rounding up Catholics. It would be liberals rounding up right-wingers and putting them on trial for hate crimes. The liberal Torquemadas would be smug and angry and self-righteous. And when they were done, they would proudly announce they had finally banished intolerance.

Ann Coulter, Slander, Liberal Lies About the American Right [Crown Publishers, 2002, p.196]


It follows that, as a historian has very wittily been called an inverted prophet, the professor of law is the inverted moralist, and therefore even jurisprudence in the proper sense, i.e., the doctrine of the rights that may be asserted, is inverted morality, in the chapter where it teaches the rights that are not to be violated. The concept of wrong and of its negation, right, which is originally moral, become juridical by shifting the starting-point from the active to the passive side, and hence by inversion. This, together with Kant's theory of law, which very falsely derives from his categorical imperative the foundation of the State as a moral duty, has even in quite recent times occasionally been the cause of that very strange error, that the State is an institution for promoting morality, that it results from the endreavour to achieve this, and that it is accordingly directed against egoism.

Arthur Schopenhauer, The World as Will and Representation, Volume I [E.F.J. Payne translation, 1958, Dover Publications, 1966, p.345]


More than half the [federal] offenses proposed, and more than three out of five of the offenses actually enacted into law, lack an adequate criminal-intent requirement. Criminal intent -- or, in lawyer-speak, mens rea -- is a fundamental and an essential element of justice in criminal law...

Any new or amended criminalization must have an adequate criminal-intent requirement. And Congress must take steps to ensure that all criminal penalties are proportionate to the harm and wrongfulness of the prohibited conduct.

Brian W. Walsh and Tiffany Joslyn, "Time to Arrest the Federal Criminalization Spree," The Wall Street Journal, January 29, 2015, A13, boldface added

Morality can be distinguished from law or from justice according to the way in which the latter is publicly enforced and sanctioned through the power of the state, while the former is regarded as a private matter where wrongs are to the moral discredit of a person but not such as to allow legal recourse for those wronged. Complaints are often made about the absence of such a distinction, that virtue or morality cannot be or ought not be legislated, or about its presence, that the decline of private morality calls for a public and legal remedy. The distinction is real enough, and its presence reveals another boundary between polynomic domains of value.

The difference between morality and justice comes not from the difference between actions and consequences (as between morality and ideal or euergetic ethics) but from the difference between motives and actions. As Kant noted, the worth of moral action is in the intention, not in what is actually done. The imperative of morality is first of all to act with good will. Even the best of good will, however, does not necessarily produce right action -- the saying is that the path to hell is paved with good intentions. And even ill will does not necessarily produce wrong action -- it is really an ad hominem fallacy to evaluate an action on the basis of an agent's motive.

The estimation of justice does not primarily concern intentions but what actually is done. There is no breach of justice unless some wrong of negligence, violence, or fraud has been committed (in law the actus reus, plural acti rei). Intention (the mens rea) then may become an issue in judging the culpability or severity of the wrong, as between various degrees of murder, where intention, malice, and forethought progressively increase the severity of the crime (to voluntary manslaughter, second degree murder, and first degree murder, respectively). If no wrong is committed, then it is not an issue of justice and motives are irrelevant.

Even undoubted wrongs of action may be "merely" moral if they are not very severe or are intrinsically difficult to prove: willful breach of an informal, oral promise for no good reason will always be a moral wrong, but only if some financial loss (or damage to public standing) or physical (or even severe enough psychological) injury results will it be a breach of an actionable "oral contract" and so a judicial wrong. There are legal rules about the factors (such as the presence of a "consideration") that must be involved if an enforceable contract is judged to exist. Breach of promise will always be morally actionable in the sense of voiced moral reproach or damage to personal relationships.

ETHICS
MORALITYEuergetic Ethics, the good and the bad: non-moral worth in human life, the good of teleological ethics, the worth and meaning of life -- things good-for-us: Hortatives --exhortations
WILLMorality of actions, right and wrong: ethics of justice; evaluation of actions in their own right; causes of judicial penalty and retribution: Imperatives -- commands
Morality of intentions, good and ill will: ethics of intention and virtue; moral evaluation of intentions; "mere" morality: Imperatives -- commands
,
kind
,
right
,
good
veracious, honest, upright righteous, good good, beautiful, pretty
Benevolence Right Good

Graphic Version of Table

The ultimate moral evaluation of an action concerns the intention. Many actions innocent in themselves may be immoral because of the motive. That motive may be difficult for other persons to know. It may even be impossible for others to know: thus the emphasis (as in the example cited by Jesus of adultery committed in the heart -- Matthew 5:27) is that morality is morality even if wrongs are known only to the agent (and to God). The moral sanction of religion, therefore, is a much different matter than the moral sanction of law. The right of privacy (and the right against self-incrimination, where a judicial wrong has been committed and the state must prove culpable motive) protects the individual's self-knowledge of motive from the law and the state. Individuals are properly at legal liberty to pursue actions that are not judicial wrongs for good reasons, bad reasons, or no reasons; and the morality of those actions is a private, personal matter, or a matter of interpersonal judgment on a level of "mere" morality.

Deal with people according to their deeds [acti rei] and not according to their words [verba]. Yet deeds are not worth the intentions which inspire them; therefore each man shall be judged according to this intentions [mens rea] and not according to his deeds.

The Book of the Thousand Nights and One Night, rendered into English from the Literal and Complete French Translation of Dr. J.C. Mardrus, by Powys Mathers, Volume I, Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1964, 1972, 1986, p.429; Latin glosses inserted.

Strict Liability

The absence of a distinction between morality and justice is a kind of moralism. The principle that all moral wrongs should be legally sanctioned as judicial wrongs, erasing the distinction between morality and justice, may be called judicial moralism. Usually this means generalizing the morality of intention into the morality of action rather than the opposite, which would simply evaluate actions as right or wrong, without qualifying the judgment by any consideration of motive or intention. The fallacy of overgeneralized intention will be examined below.

First, the latter move, the generalization of actions into all of morality, does happen.
MORALITY=ACTIONS
judicial moralism
de-moralized
WILL
Morality, right and wrong: justice; evaluation of actions; causes of judicial penalty and retribution
[intentions and motives do not count]
Imperatives -- commands
In tort law it is called "strict liability," and some legal scholars, including Richard Epstein, believe all torts should be interpreted according to strict liability, eliminating the need to prove negligence, which otherwise is necessary to prove a tort (i.e. a civil wrong that is not the result of a breach of contract). This is not right. But what is much worse and more dangerous is that strict liability would also make things much easier for prosecutors in criminal cases; and it is now becoming common for laws to be passed that ignore motives and intentions -- the classical mens rea, the "guilty" or "actionable" mind.

Thus, "money laundering" laws, which require reporting to the government the transfers of certain amounts of cash or bearer financial instruments, although supposedly written to catch drug dealers and their agents, are typically enforced against innocent people who are either ignorant of such an obscure law or who do not believe their financial privacy in the course of innocent transactions is any of the government's business. Also, there have been several recent cases where small businesses making cash deposits at their banks, where their insurance will not cover them carrying more than $10,000 in cash, have had their bank accounts seized on the principle that they are not allowed by the money laundering laws to "structure" their deposits in increments smaller than $10,000, when the requirement to report cash desposits kicks in.

But it doesn't matter how innocent the money or the motives are. This trend in criminal law is, of course, a monstrous and despicable act of tyranny and injustice. Fortunately, the courts sometimes revoke these unjust seizures; but other judges are perfectly willing to wave them through, as though grotesque violations of natural justice and age-old principles of the common law are of no concern. These seizures are also symptoms of the misuse of "civil forfeiture" law, where property can be seized without criminal charges ever proved or even filed, violating the 14th Amendment.

Nevertheless, in 2010 these injustices became common enough, especially in Federal law, that The Economist has taken note of it:

In many [federal] criminal cases, the common-law requirement that a defendant must have a mens rea (i.e. he must or should know that he is doing wrong) has been weakened or erased. ["Too many laws, too many prisoners," July 24th-30th 2010, p.28]

Even my students often used to know the ancient legal principle, "No crime without criminal intent." The principle in Latin is:  Actus non facit reum, nisi mens sit rea, "The act does not make guilt [reum], unless there is a guilty [rea] mind." But now federal judges seem to be ignorant of this. Since they cannot actually be ignorant of it, they willfully fail to employ the tools the law provides to combat the unjust laws that many of them know are enforced through their own courts. The whole notion of "strict liability crimes" is improper and unjust.

This prnciple was quoted by Sheldon Cooper (Jim Parsons) on the television show The Big Bang Theory [2007-2019] when he appeared in court to contest a traffic ticket he had received for driving Penny (Kaley Cuoco) to the emergency room, even though he didn't have a driver's license. Sheldon being Sheldon, he didn't realize that it was not enough to cite the legal principle. He needed to argue how it applied in his case, especially a matter of "necessity," since Penny needed urgent medical attention. Instead, Sheldon displayed his typical arrogance and insulted the judge. Not a good idea. After being cited for contempt of court, and briefly imprisoned, he was unable to make his case.

On 27 September 2011 The Wall Street Journal featured a long article on the erosion of the mens rea principle of justice with a front page article, "As Federal Crime List Grows, Threshold of Guilt Declines." The continuation of the column on page 12 was headlined, "Age-Old Legal Principle Declines." The Journal says, "Lawmakers on both sides of the aisle worry about the weakening of mens rea." However, this hasn't prevented Congress from continuing to pass laws that are defective in this respect, or prevented the Courts from upholding them. One Court ruled that "knowing" conduct in a firearms case simply meant the defendant "knew" he had the firearms, not that it was illegal for him to possess them.

This is pure sophistry, apparently from judges willing to void traditional principles of justice just so the government can create criminals out of people who have insensibly run afoul of a vast and incomprehensible United States Code (or simply the obscure regulations published in the infinite pages of the Federal Register). The Journal article, however, implied rather than stated that this trend is not simply contrary to an "age-old legal principle," but that it is productive of multiple cases of grotesque injustice. This could well be one of the fruits of the judicial positivism (a form of moral heteronomy) that is taught in the law schools, that (1) there is no law but "positive" (i.e. statutory) law, and (2) "justice" is the practice of the courts, i.e. whatever it is that the courts happen do.

Lest anyone think that this is only a problem in the United States, and that The Economist can look down on these Yankee follies from the superior perspective of British law, the same trend is evident in its own land, the place of the very origin of the Common Law:

In 2009 a former soldier, Paul Clarke, found a bag in his garden containing a shotgun. He brought it to the [British] police station and was immediately handcuffed and charged with possession of the gun. At his trial the judge noted: "In law there is no dispute that Mr. Clarke has no defense to this charge. The intention of anybody possessing a firearm is irrelevant." Mr. Clarke was sentenced to five years in prison. A public outcry eventually won his release. ["Two Cautionary Tales of Gun Control," Joyce Lee Malcolm, The Wall Street Journal, 27 December 2012]

Since "in law" Mr. Clarke did have a defense, namely the absence of mens rea, and his role as a citizen enforcing the law, we must consider what sort of fool or tool is this judge. But we do owe him credit for a clear statement of the fallacy that he promulgates, namely that "the intention of anybody possessing a firearm is irrelevant." This is strict liability with a vengeance, in a case where "possession" has itself been interpreted in a way that defies common sense. Perhaps the police cannot be expected to exercise common sense, but it is certainly the office of a competent judge to supply any deficiency. Instead, this British judge is morally and legally incompetent, in line with something we see more of in law these days, which is the mindless application of senseless rules, by people who often seem to be proud and self-righteous about what they are doing.

Judges cannot plead that their "hands are tied" by the present state of law, for they have multiple levels of recourse, certainly in American law, when dealing with injustices like "strict liability crimes":

  1. Bite the bullet and rule that the law is unconstitutional.
  2. Rule that the law cannot be enforced without taking the mens rea into account.
  3. Hand down a directed verdict of not guilty.
  4. Dismiss the case with prejudice, so that it cannot be refiled.
  5. Instruct the Jury that it has the power to return a verdict of not guilty if they think that the law violates a just requirement of mens rea.
  6. Dismiss the case without prejudice, which means it could be refiled. And,
  7. Recuse himself, so that the case will pass to another judge.

If a judge is fearful for his career, the first two or three, or even four, alternatives may frighten him. A judicial conduct authority may sanction him. In fiction at least, we sometimes see the first alternative, such as when the beloved Ray Walston (1914–2001), playing Judge Henry Bone on the television series Picket Fences (1992-1996), was willing to rule on the constitutionality of laws that had already been accepted as constitutional by the Courts. The fearful judge (which is what we expect from the judge as bureaucrat), however, can always take the seventh alternative and recuse himself without expalantion. The last I heard, there were at least 50 federal judges refusing to take non-violent drug cases.

Unfortunately, what is more common these days is that judges enter into the spirit of tyranny and politically motivated revenge, regardless of the requirements or sound traditions of justice or even conscience. They are willing to distort law, righteousness, and justice in order to help the prosecution, behind which there is a political antipathy towards actions that are not wrongful, sometimes on the pretext that destroying people's lives may be a "social good."

Judicial Moralism of Belief

Judicial Moralism as the generalization of intentions into all of morality, although just as vicious as the "strict liability" generalization of actions over intentions, has historically been much more common. Religions have typically been guilty of such moralism, and have controlled or pressured political authorities to enforce it; but there has been no lack of purely secular ideologies, from the French Revolution to Communism to present Political Correctness, that have tried to enforce their views as a political program apart from any religion.
MORALITY=INTENTIONS
judicial moralism
WILL=MORALITY[actions de-moral-ized]
Morality, good and ill will: intention and virtue; all moral evaluation only of intentions
Moralism of belief: Certain things must be believedMoralism of
feeling: Certain feelings are forbidden or required
Imperatives -- commands
Judicial moralism thus tends to be a characteristic of both religious moralism and political moralism.

Furthermore, each characteristically becomes a way of morally judging, not just actions and even intentions, but beliefs. That is because good or bad intentions always go with beliefs about what is good or bad. Since judicial moralism collapses intention and act, the actual requirement of justice to act justly is transferred to the mental state. What is the proper moral issue in that state is good or bad will; but for judicial moralism more is required than that, since good will doesn't have anything like the content, structure, or definiteness of a good or bad act. Consequently, judicial moralism focuses on the beliefs that condition the will, something as definite in the mental state as the act was externally.

Thus the moral requirement becomes one of correct belief -- the actual meaning of the Greek word ὀρθοδοξία, orthodoxía -- orthodoxy -- as the sign of good will. Incorrect belief, ἑτεροδοξία, heterodoxía -- heterodoxy -- then obviously signifies ill will, and all the commendation and reward or condemnation and punishment that should only focus on good or bad deeds instead becomes focused on these correct or incorrect beliefs. And we all know how heresy, αἵρεσις, haíresis, is worse than simple disbelief -- since the former is a kind of fraud, while the latter is only ignorance -- so those who knowingly defy orthodoxy should be punished severely indeed. As it happens, "heresy," αἵρεσις, itself means "choice" or "taking for oneself," which means will, wicked will. We know how people have been burned at the stake for this kind of thing.

The past decade saw the rise of the woke progressives who dictate what words can be said and ideas held, thus poisoning and paralyzing American humor, drama, entertainment, culture [literature, scholarship] and journalism. In the coming 10 years someone will effectively stand up to them. They are the most hated people in America, and their entire program is accusation: you are racist, sexist, homophobic, transphobic [& Islamophobic]; you are a bigot, a villain, a white male, a [cisnormative] patriarchal misogynist, your day is over. They never have a second move. Bow to them, as most do, and they'll accuse you even more of newly imagined sins. They claim to be vulnerable victims, and moral. Actually they're not. They're mean ["cry bullies"] and seek to kill, and like all bullies are cowards.

Everyone with an honest mind hates them. Someone will finally move effectively against them. Who? How? That will be a story of the '20s, and a good one.

Peggy Noonan, "Warren Zevon's Wisdom for the 2020s," The Wall Street Journal, January 4-5, 2020, A13; extra features added in brackets; a good first blow was the "Sticks & Stones" comedy special by Dave Chappelle, on Netflix [2019]. This was very, indeed exceptionally, popular and successful, but hated by the .

Unfortunately, Peggy Noonan, out of personal hatred of President Trump, has now turned her back on Republican voters and become an apologist for the Democrat socialists, the raving anti-Semities in Congress, and their corrupt, senile President. She has assumed the sage stance of many RINO's of advising Republicans how to win elections by being, or at least talking, more like Democrats. In 2023, Noonan has even repeated Democrat talking points to praise Biden's mendacious and pathetic State of the Union speech.


On "Constitution Day," September 13, 2017, Carolyn Rouse, Chair of the Department of Anthropology and Director of the Program in African Studies at Princeton University, gave a lecture titled "F%*# Free Speech, An Anthropologist’s Take on Campus Speech Debates." Among other things, she said:

Culture is what helps us determine the appropriateness of speech by balancing our rights as enshrined in the Constitution with understandings of context.... the way in which free speech is being celebrated in the media makes little to no sense anthropologically... Language is partial. It relies on context for comprehensibility, and can have implications that go far beyond simply hurting somebody’s feelings. Put simply, speech is costly. So, contrary to the ACLU’s statement on their website regarding the role of free speech on college campuses, the academy has never promoted free speech as its central value.

Such views might warrant a "Dear Colleague" letter from the Civil Rights Division of the Department of Education, inquiring whether this meant Professor Rouse therefore intends to "balance" the Civil Rights of her students and colleagues with other, perhaps "anthropological," considerations. As a recipient of federal money, Princeton University is bound to respect the Civil Rights of its faculty, staff, and students; and if Professor Rouse ever violated those Civil Rights, Princeton might suffer loss of federal funds or be the target of a Civil Rights lawsuit. Professor Rouse said that the purpose of her lecture was to "rethink academic freedom and academic values"; but she better "rethink" her "values" if her intention is to violate the protected, Constitutional freedoms of those around her.

Ἐγκλινοβάραγγος (Enklinobarangus)


As a scientist, I'd much rather have questions I can't answer than answers I can't question.

Mark Tegmark, MIT, 2020; similar saying attributed to Richard Feynman (1918-1988), povenance undetermined.


That’s Musk’s dream. And Trump’s. And Putin’s. And the dream of every dictator, strongman, demagogue and modern-day robber baron on Earth. For the rest of us, it would be a brave new nightmare.

Robert Reich, "Elon Musk's Vision for the Internet is Dangerous Nonsense," The Guardian, 12 Apr 2022; condemning Musk for promising free speech at Twitter.

The libertarian vision of an 'uncontrolled' internet is not the dream of dictators...

[Robert] Reich begins by condemning Russian President Vladimir Putin's authoritarianism: how he hides the truth from the people of Russia by outlawing dissent, jailing protesters, and prioritizing government propaganda over independent media. Reich then turns his attention to former President Donald Trump, writing that the decisions by social media companies to ban the president "were necessary to protect American democracy."

But wait a minute: Why does silencing a political viewpoint protect democracy? How is that any different than Putin saying his silencing of dissenters is necessary to protect Russia? Reich doesn't seem to realize that he is condemning one kind of tyranny while lionizing another, which leads him into a very, very odd attack on Tesla CEO Elon Musk, who recently became the largest shareholder of Twitter after buying a 9 percent stake in the company.

Robby Soave, "Robert Reich Smears Elon Musk's Vision for Twitter as 'Dangerous Nonsense'," Reason, 13 April 2022.

In the Orwellian ideology of the Left, as with Robert Reich, "free speech" is the tool of Fascism, despite the fact that Fascism, Communism, and other dictatorships have never allowed free speech. So the Left is against it for the same reason as the dictators. Musk, of course, completed his purchase of Twitter and then released documents showing Twitter practicing censorship as instructed by the FBI and other government agencies. This was illegal. Reich claims that Musk is only after "power"; but it is censorship that expresses power, not free speech. So Reich pretends to oppose power, when what he and his comrades want is to have and use it.

This is all part of the new meaning the "Big Lie." Joseph Goebbels is supposed to have said, "If you tell a lie big enough and keep repeating it, people will eventually come to believe it." It is not clear he actually said this, but the principle has often been invoked, and practiced. However, the "Big Lie" now is not a matter of repetition or anyone believing it. With enough power, a lie only needs to be asserted once, and the repetition is then required as a matter of obedience, not belief. It was Josef Stalin who perfected this. The "Party Line" could change day by day, or even minute by minute, and the faithful will immediately parrot it verbatim, just as the New York Times repeats Democrat talking points. The bigger and more transparent the lie, the more it demonstrates power. Its obvious falsehood will be irrelevant. Skeptics are criminals.

Thus, when Barack Obama was running for President in 2008, no major Democrat politician was in favor of "gay marriage." In California, voters had even outlawed "gay marriage," although allowing its practical equivalent in "domestic partnerships." However, when "gay marriage" was mandated by the Supreme Court in 2015, it immediately became a political crime to oppose it; and traditional religions, including ʾIslām, that didn't even recognize "gay rights," let alone "gay marriage," were demonized as "fascist," "bigoted," "Nazis," etc. (except, actually, ʾIslām, which was above criticism).

Part of the Big Lie now is what is frequently called "gaslighting." This goes back to the classic movie Gaslight [1944], where the heroine (Ingrid Bergman) notices that the gaslights dim, even though no one else is supposed to be in the house, and her murderous husband (Charles Boyer) tells her she is imagining things. Thus, "gaslighting" today involves telling lies that can easily be disconfirmed by one's own knowledge or experience, while the liar expects to be believed, or obeyed, nevertheless. This can be involved in either the Goebbels or the Stalin sort of Big Lie. In the movie, the heroine is expected to begin doubting her own sanity; and in today's politics, where so much is simply insane, certain politicians or activists may rely on their own folly being a kind of contagion. In some jurisdictions, like California or Manhattan, where political insanity rises to levels of self-harm, they may be right about that.

The idea that falsehood in the cause of power may be as good as, if not better, than the truth goes back to Nietzsche. The practice can also be found in "deconstruction," but Nietzsche was at least open and honest about it, while "post-modern" and Marxist "critical" theorists are not.

Ἐγκλινοβάραγγος


A professor at a Michigan university has been suspended after a disturbing Facebook post that encouraged killing “right-wing” speakers who spout [so-called] racist, homophobic or anti-transgender viewpoints.

Steven Shaviro, who teaches English and film studies at Wayne State University in Detroit, took to Facebook this week to say that it was ineffective for students to simply protest speakers they disagree with because it gives the orators “publicity and validation.”

“Although I do not advocate violating federal and state criminal codes, I think it is far more admirable to kill a racist, homophobic, or transphobic speaker than it is to shout them down,” Shaviro explained in a since-deleted post.

In an email to students Monday, Wayne State president Dr. M. Roy Wilson said the university found Shaviro’s comments “at best, morally reprehensible and, at worst, criminal.”

"Professor suspended after saying it would be ‘more admirable to kill’ racist speakers than protest," "‘Kill foes’ prof put on break," The New York Post, March 29, 2023, p.9; color added.


To the Left, conservative or libertarian speech is "violence," while Leftist violence -- including assaults, arson, and looting -- are protected "speech." Recently, a Hunter College professor, Shellyne Rodriguez, after calling anti-abortion pamphlets "violent," and brushing the display off the table, demonstrated this with a machete against a New York Post reporter who had knocked on her door (as we see) -- also chasing the reporter and camera crew down the street, waving the machete. Hunter College fired her, but the faculty association voiced their full support, thereby apparently endorsing violence -- not just words -- against students and reporters. Modern "education" in action.

Ἐγκλινοβάραγγος


University of Rhode Island professor Erik Loomis defended the murder of a conservative protester and said he saw “nothing wrong” with such acts of violence.

The university later elevated Loomis to director of graduate studies of history.

He continued to espouse such views as denouncing “science, statistics, and technology [as] all inherently racist.”

Jonathan Turley, "Only thing shocking about machete attack was a college actually firing a woke professor," "The Nutty Professor, Prof's Mayhem," The New York Post, May 25, 2023, p.12; Shellyne Rodriguez pursues reporter out into the street, continuing to wave machete.


If ignorance is a disease, Harvard Yard is the Wuhan wet market.

Bill Maher, "Real Time with Bill Maher," HBO, October 20, 2023.


Truth is treason in the empire of lies.

Georege Orwell, Ron Paul

Free Speech

In denying judicial moralism we affirm that it cannot be a moral duty to believe any particular propositions. This is the moral basis of the principles of freedom of conscience and free speech. Morality requires us to mean well and to do what is right, but believing things in good will and good faith is about truth, which has its own standards of evidence and justification, not about meaning well or doing anything, let alone choosing a belief.

While it is common now for people to talk about "freedom of expression" rather than "freedom of speech," the First Amendment says "speech," and it is speech that is particularly under attack from the Stalinists in 2021. "Freedom of expression" sounds like what would protect strippers, not just speakers. I'm all for that; but it is not the main issue.
Freedom of Speech, 1943, Norman Rockwell (1894-1978), National Archives at College Park

As Thomas Jefferson said, "The opinions and belief of men depend not on their own will, but follow involuntarily the evidence proposed to their minds." It cannot be a duty to believe what is true because whatever is believed is already believed to be true:  The evidence, experience, or authority upon which one's beliefs are based are reasonably to be changed, not by some independent act of moral will, but by demonstrably better evidence, experience, or authority. And it is always a good question just what is true and just what is better evidence, experience, and authority. As Socrates says, "for clearly, if I learn better, I shall cease to do what I am doing unwilling" [Apology, 26a]. Meanwhile, πείσομαι δὲ μᾶλλον τῷ θεῷ ἢ ὑμῖν, "I will obey the god rather than you" [29d].

The only thing that can be a duty is to try and find out what is true and then to be steadfast in the truth as that is understood; but that very steadfastness may be perceived as wickedness by others who are differently persuaded by their understanding. Indeed, while the prudent may conceal opinions that would be condemned as heretical, perhaps with fearful consequences, the totalitarian mindset cannot tolerate mere silence ("Silence is violence," is now the totalitarian slogan). Potential heretics must be tested with demands for confessions of orthodoxy. Thus, violations of free speech, not only are those that sanction the expression of honest opinion, they are those that demand that conformity be made explicit, under duress. In the decay of American democracy in 2020 and 2021, militant mobs may demand of spectators or passersby that they affirm the latest leftist shibboleths, under harrassment, intimidation, and threat. The authorities, cowardly, complicit, or intimidated themselves, do little to combat this.

It was a case of judicial moralism that the Catholic Church argued it was a moral duty for Galileo to confess that the earth was at the center of the universe, why Pope Clement VIII abhored both the Edict of Nantes (see above) and the whole idea of "liberty of conscience," and how even today some people argue against the Darwinian theory of evolution simply because they think "survival of the fittest" makes for unacceptable moral consequences in society. "Political correctness," of course, is a name for moralistic political orthodoxy, enforced by punitive sanctions, if not, sometimes, death.

Thus, freedom of conscience means that one cannot be commanded or morally coerced to believe anything in particular; and freedom of speech means that one cannot be prohibited, by law, force, or threat, from speaking the truth. The traditional justifications for free speech, e.g. that we want vigorous debate or that more speech is the remedy for any "bad" speech, are beside the point. Political purposes are not moral principles. They are thus not strong enough, and they are vulnerable to the changing tides of politics.

Also, the traditional idea of an "exception" to free speech, such as shouting "fire" in a crowded theater, is also besides the point and even confused; for shouting "fire" is the right and proper thing to do in the case of a fire, while what is properly prohibited is shouting "fire" where there is no fire, which is not just false but fraudulent speech, intended to deceive and cause harm. Using speech for fraudulent and harmful purposes, with lies or deception, is morally and often criminally wrongful. If your intent is to harm or defraud, with false and deceptive statements, you are not protected by the right of free speech.

Notice that a lie is a choice. Good faith beliefs and contents of speech may not be acts of will, and so are not subject to moral evaluation, but lies are acts of will, which are made with ends in view. These acts and ends then fall within the sphere of moral evaluation. If you lie to avoid hurting someone's feelings, this may actually only be good manners and the manifestation of care for the feelings of others. But lies pursuant to criminal fraud, or that are careless of the harm that may be caused, as in the crowded theater, are not innocent, or protected. This is a very bright line. If one choses to lie, this is an actus reus that calls for the moral evaluation of the mens rea [note].

Furthermore, in denying judicial moralism, not only cannot we say that it is a moral duty to believe propositions about possible matters of fact that are open to question and to rational or empirical testing or determination, but we cannot even say it is a moral duty to believe propositions about matters of value or about the nature or content of morality itself. Thus, although the moral consequences of the views of Friedrich Nietzsche are very bad, he does not seem to have been a bad person himself and cannot be morally condemned just for thinking mistaken thoughts -- Will Durant even called him "a warrior with the heart of a girl," which no Nietzschean would regard as a compliment. Martin Heidegger, of course, is another matter, since his actions, as a member of the Nazi Party, as well as his thoughts are at issue.

A person who means well and whose actions are above reproach but who professes moral views that seem to us mistaken is not to be punished but to be persuaded. That is our duty. We may fear that they will end up doing wrong because of their beliefs, but if only beliefs are in question, the only remedy is the truth as we understand it. If we cannot persuade them, we must even be sensible of the possibility that we are wrong rather than they. If our real duty is to find out the truth, then intellectual complacency and self-righteousness are moral wrongs of negligence -- and anyone who thinks that they are less likely suffer from those failings than their ideological opponents is a fool.

If we morally or legally condemn beliefs that are held in good faith and accompany no judicial wrongs, we have created a category of "thought crimes."
MORALITY=INTENTIONS
judicial moralism
WILL=MORALITY[actions de-moral-ized]
Morality, good and ill will: intention and virtue; all moral evaluation only of intentions
Moralism of belief: Certain things must be believed: thought crimesMoralism of feeling: Certain feelings are forbidden or required
Imperatives -- commands
That is an inevitable result of judicial moralism; and in its terms, loss of freedom of speech is a small thing in comparison to loss of freedom of thought. It is not surprising that the expression "thought crime" began in the context of severe and totalitarian political moralism -- shockingly reincarnated in the political correctness of the modern American college campus -- although the idea is as old as the concept of heresy. And we don't need to read much history to find that heretics were always regarded as the most depraved and vicious of people, although historically they often seem less cruel and vicious than their persecutors. Interestingly, Jesus says "You will know them [the false prophets] by their fruits" (Matthew 7:16): not by their words, but by their deeds (as he continues at 7:21).

The tendency, indeed, of judicial moralism is not only to moralize and legalize beliefs but to demoralize actions: the deed becomes relatively unimportant besides the willingness to confess, affirm, and witness to orthodoxy, whether religious or political. Someone of "sound views" becomes preferable even to someone who refrains from wrong. As Paul Johnson says of Lenin in Modern Times [HarperPerennial, 1991], "He judged men not by their moral qualities but by their views, or rather the degree to which they accepted his" [p.51]. Of course, this is usually what judical moralism amounts to, "You have a duty to believe what I do." Thus George Orwell wrote:

Actions are held good or bad, not on their own merits but according to who does them, and there is almost no kind of outrage -- torture, the use of hostages, forced labor, mass deportations, imprisonment without trial, forgery, assassinations, the bombing of civilians -- which does not change its moral color when it is committed by "our" side. [Quoted by Paul Hollander, The Survival of the Adversary Culture, Transaction Publishers, 1991, p. 123]

The principal justification for attacking beliefs instead of actions and for making rules against good faith speech, when laws already exist against violence, fraud, vandalism, etc. (judicial wrongs), is that such beliefs cause such actions. We must get at the root of things, after all, the argument might go. But besides the moralism of such an approach, to morally condemn beliefs as such without addressing their claim to truth, this approach is deeply dehumanizing and irresponsible. That people act from certain causes is a judgment made by science but not normally by morality, since morality holds persons responsible for their actions and intentions regardless of the causes, unless they are to be judged actually incompetent. The insane act out of causes that relieve them of moral responsibility. It is then particularly paradoxical to morally condemn someone for having acted on the basis of a cause that nevertheless is to be treated more like a disease or a tumor to be excised, through authoritative therapy (re-education, etc.), than like an adult, competent belief to be answered with rational argument and knowledge. Reducing people to the puppets of causation not only completely erases their moral dignity, autonomy, and rationality but substitutes an authoritarian, totalitarian source of standards that in principle must be accepted without argument or objection.

The category of thought crime has recently been revived in American colleges and universities in the "political correctness" movement, whose major project has been to write and enforce speech codes (which, for public institutions, are then typically thrown out by the courts as unconstitutional). The public justification for such codes has been to fight hate crimes and to punish hate related insults, harassment, assaults, vandalism, etc. The motive for such codes and the practice of their application, however, often seem to amount to simple hostility towards opposing political beliefs. They embody an ideological animus (founded in judicial moralism) that is willing to vilify and stigmatize even reasonably argued political opinions, and people, as racist, sexist, homophobic (expanding limitlessly into a circus of political crimes, "classism," "lookism," "sizeism," "speciesism," "orientalism," etc.). In short, they seem to seek the criminalization of mere beliefs and the people who may express them in good will and good faith. In that project terms like "racism" and "sexism" become no more than chanted slogans used for smearing opponents and for eliminating the need for argument or debate, since of course no one need take the views or persons of racists or sexists, etc. seriously. They deserve, like neo-Nazis and Klansmen, to be driven out of honest venues (like colleges, universities, and the media) and prosecuted for the damage their ideas do. The only escape from such condemnations is to become "re-educated" or "sensitized" and affirm the politically correct line without reservations.

The political correctness movement, consequently, represents the continuing political and legal threat of judicial moralism to free thought and free speech. Fortunately, even most politicians (even Democrats -- although this may have changed) recognize the totalitarian origins of this movement, although supposedly educated academics often don't. In 2015, even President Barack Obama, whom many suspect of harboring an anti-American ideology, rebuked students for not respecting free speech, at a time when some student leaders openly disdain the First Amendment.

Judicial Moralism of Feeling

Similar to the judicial moralism of commanding or condemning beliefs is a judicial moralism of commanding or condemning feelings. It can be no moral duty to feel a certain way since feelings are not voluntary and cannot be "corrected" through an act of will. Thus, Aristotle said, "Again, we are not angry or afraid from choice, but the virtues are certain modes of choice, or at all events involve choice" [Nicomachean Ethics, Book II, v, 4, Loeb Classical Library, Harvard U. Press, 1926-1982, pp.88-89].
MORALITY=INTENTIONS
judicial moralism
WILL=MORALITY[actions de-moral-ized]
Morality, good and ill will: intention and virtue; all moral evaluation only of intentions
Moralism of belief: Certain things must be believed: thought crimesMoralism of feeling: Certain feelings are forbidden or required: "hate" crimes
Imperatives -- commands
Nevertheless, in this, traditional morality often misleads us. We find both Leviticus (19:18) and Jesus commanding love of neighbors and enemies (Matthew 5:44), and Jesus forbidding anger (Matthew 5:22). Confucius also simply commands, "Love others" (Analects XII 22:1). Not only is this basically impossible but it leads to a inappropriate guilt, when it cannot be done, that is morally damaging.

The genuine moral concern about anger, as in our concern about someone's temper, is if it leads to uncontrolled behavior, i.e. violence and judicial wrongs of action. All sorts of feelings -- anger, liking, dislike, love, sympathy, hatred -- can go with either good intention and right action or bad intention and wrong action. In other words, the imperative of morality is to mean to deal justly and to do so, regardless of one's feelings. This is sometimes confused by the way that "hatred" and "ill will" can be equated with meaning to do harm and so with bad moral intention. However, few would evaluate their hatred or ill will towards Hitler or Stalin as involving an immoral intention (although according to Jesus it actually would). Our assumption is that evil persons merit hatred and ill will and that this is not to morally wrong them or maintain an immoral intention. Our hatred is because they deserve harm as just retribution for their wrongful actions (although this again violates Jesus's injunction not to judge, Matthew 7:1). Intending them harm is therefore simply to desire retributive justice. Since feelings actually are caused, often by certain beliefs, condemnation of feelings also becomes a way of indirectly condemning beliefs. Treating the "causes" of hatred thus can become the authoritarian "re-education" of political thought crimes.

Hate Crimes

Moralizing feelings may become a problem when we identify certain acts of violence, vandalism, etc. as "hate crimes." "Hate crimes" form a legitimate moral and legal category, but the proper formulation of the matter is obscured by the way in which it is usually presented and discussed. In any crime malice can be an aggravating factor. This is just what distinguishes murder from manslaughter. A "hate crime," however, is one where some specific source of malice is of concern, namely, hatred based on ethnicity, race, religion, national origin, or differences of sex or sexual preference. Malice for those reasons, and not for reasons of hatred of individuals, is now often considered particularly aggravating as much for reasons for social policy as for reasons of moral culpability. The laws are especially intended to discourage ethnic, racial, etc. hatred because this is considered a social problem, and because of the modern confusion that private individuals can violate the "civil rights" of others ("hate crime" laws are often proposed as federal "civil rights" legislation). But if the purpose of such laws is thus some social end, it is questionable whether it is in accord with justice to magnify a punishment for some purpose other than just retribution. It is also questionable whether increased punishments will effectively serve their social purpose any more than draconian punishments ever have. After all, it is actually an argument against the death penalty that even the prospect of death does not really deter murderers [note].

While we may very well see malice motivated by hatreds as a morally and judicially aggravating condition in crimes and use a principle that there are special "hate crimes," if some "hates" are singled out over others for political reasons, this puts us onto ground perilously fraught with the possibility of judicial moralism. The abuse of this principle is easy, especially when the rhetorical sophistry is always handy that criticism of the category of "hate crimes" is the same as condoning the wrongful acts of violence, vandalism, etc. that it concerns. On the other hand, what we are dealing with in hate crimes is really not a matter of "hate" at all. The moral violation of attacking someone because of their ethnic or racial identity is actually not a violation of right based on belief or feeling. Calling such violations "hate crimes" introduces a misdirection into our analysis.

For the right perspective, we must consider some circumstances under which the belief and the hatred are justified, as in the feelings that Jews might have for Germans, Armenians for Turks, Irish for British, Chinese for Japanese, Lithuanians for Russians, Sikhs for Moslems and Hindus, etc., all based on real historical crimes that resulted in the deaths of many of the aggrieved groups. Germans really did kill Jews, Turks Armenians, Japanese Chinese, etc. So does that mean that it is morally acceptable, as retribution, that Jews could just start killing Germans, and so forth? Of course not. Members of a group of people, of any kind, are not responsible for crimes committed by some other members of the group. While we may see a group, in a general way, committing crimes, those responsible for the crimes are those who actually perpetrate them, not others who do not perpetrate them, especially when the non-perpetrators may be members of the group in the distant future [note].

The moral principle, then, is that the retributions of justice, whether formal or irregular, can only be visited on actual responsible individual perpetrators. A "hate crime" is consequently not an error of hate or of belief but a moral error of singling out some individual as worthy of attack, not because of some wrong he is known to have done himself, but because of some wrong some other member or members of his group are believed to have done.

If that is so, then it should be clear that the remedy for "hate crimes" cannot always be to try and get people to stop hating each other. No amount of education is going to get Armenians to stop hating the Turks. Indeed, real education is liable to intensify the hatred, once the facts of history are known, since people tend to forget the details of crimes in the past. Thus we should be suspicious when we see that with the magnified punishments for hate crimes (which to an extent may be appropriate for the fundamental nature of the moral error involved) also go programs designed to eliminate ethnic, racial, etc. hatreds through education, sensitivity training, etc. The assumption is that simply knowing enough about other ethnic groups, or life-styles, etc., will remove the conflicts. It may well be that in cases of baseless bigotry knowledge of the simple truth will make a difference, but to generalize this to all cases of hatreds and conflict involves incredibly naive and ahistorical assumptions; and it clearly involves a formulation of the category of hate crimes that heads it in the direction of judicial moralism of belief and of feeling, instead of in the proper direction of respect for innocent individuals. Half the trouble in the world today seems to involve peoples who have lived with each other for centuries and certainly know each other all too well: Catholic and Protestant Irish, Moslem and Hindu Indians, Greek and Turkish Cypriots, Serbs and Croats, Christian and Moslem Bosnians, Armenians and Azeris, Tamils and Sinhalese, Basques and Spanish, Tibetans and Chinese, Eritreans and Ethiopians, etc. Where we find unity among diverse people, it is always because of some overriding loyalty: Malcolm X found blacks and whites at peace together on the pilgrimage to Mecca because of the cultural and religious unity of Islām. Moslem pilgrims even wear the same clothes.

But today, it is often claimed that harmony results from emphasizing differences and diversity and even denying that there is or ought to be anything that imposes some overall ("hegemonic") unity. This is an ignorant prescription for nothing but increasing conflict and hatred, wherever it is applied. Differences breed aesthetic variety, and aesthetic variety (even apart from histories of crime and conflict) breeds likes and dislikes, even loves and hates. That is the aesthetic truth of human life and is perfectly innocent in itself. Those dislikes, etc. can only be suppressed by the most ferocious anaesthetic or judicial moralism, which will persuade few and have little enough effect in any case. Even without serious issues of conflict, culture and "lifestyle" will always be inevitable hinges of aesthetic preference. The unity, in turn, which is the only hope of peace and justice, is the principle of morality itself, the respect for the autonomy of others regardless of likes and dislikes, loves and hates, cultural or ethnic identity, or personal practices. The project of morality is to clearly distinguish those things, not to judicially moralize the aesthetic dimension of feelings and preferences. To appreciate the beauty of another culture can be a major hortative good, but it cannot be a moral imperative. Confusing justice with aesthetics all too easily has the unintended consequence, not of morally abolishing hatred, but of moralizing hatred into fanatical and violent self-righteousness.

But if Jews or Armenians do not have the right to attack Germans or Turks, what if they do not wish to associate with them? Well, we certainly can't make them. Or can we? What if Jews or Armenians own businesses and don't want to hire or serve Germans or Turks? Right now they could be sued for discriminating according to "national origin." Thus our laws as written actually try to force people to associate with each other even if they don't want to do so and even if their reasons for not wanting to are based on major traumas of history. We might say that they don't have any reason to hate specific individual Germans or Turks any more than they have any right to attack them in retribution for the wrongs of history, but that is precisely to commit the fallacy of judicial moralism of feeling: people are going to feel the way they feel for whatever reason, and ill feelings for a group are inevitably going to tend to be applied to all members of the group. Morality can only forbid the action, not the feeling; and the actions that can be forbidden are only the ones causing harm through violence, coercion, fraud, or negligence, not ones merely of a refusal to deal with or associate with someone. Freedom of association lessens conflicts by allowing people who don't like each other to separate. Forcing people to associate out of the notion that this is going to make them learn to like each other is not only tyrannical but a formula for civil strife. In small, intensely controlled contexts, as in the military, this may work to an extent; but we often see how conflict can still explode even under military discipline -- and it is a very bad sign when political activists take comfort that society could be reformed if subjected to something very much like military discipline.

The passion and violence that accompany religious and political moralism, and especially their dimension as judicial moralism of belief and feeling, are as much with us as ever. The saying is that politics and religion are not things people should discuss in polite company, but that simply is the result of the difficulty we have in separating the evaluation of the truth of beliefs from value judgments about moral or judicial worth. Here we can only labor to avoid judicial moralism and to attempt to review with some dispassion the issues we consider, remembering that beliefs and propositions must be answered with reason and evidence, not with self-righteous moral condemnation.

Sexual Preference

One category of "hate crimes" that the principle offered does not cover is that involving "sexual preference." Crimes against homosexuals cannot be said to involve an error of thinking that the individuals are not engaged in the practices that the group is thought to be guilty of, since practicing homosexuals indeed engage in homosexual practices. Since the Bible itself mandates the killing of male homosexuals and it is regarded by very many people as a proper source of morality, even of law, one cannot say that all "gay bashing" is done in bad faith or merely out of malice. That the Bible is not a proper source of secular law should now be obvious, but it is not to all persons of good will; and as philosophers cannot agree on what the proper source of secular law and morality is (many asserting that there is no proper source), the case for Biblical morality would tend to be strengthened in the eyes of many.

Meanwhile, people who demonize Christians for doing no more than morally condemning homosexual practices, or opposing "gay marriage," often wink at the fierce suppression of homosexuality, and the actual execution of homosexuals or forced marriages of lesbians, in Islām. This is the hypocrisy of the Left that results from the identification of "Islamophobia" as a political (thought/hate) crime, mainly just because radical Islām is anti-American, which makes it an ally in the great war against capitalism and "imperialism." As Mark Steyn has observed, the fraternal acceptance of Jihadist savagery apparently trumps all the other political and social values of the Left.

If crimes against homosexuals do not qualify as "hate crimes," does this mean they are simply to be allowed? Of course not. The idea of "hate crimes" merely adds an aggrevating factor to something that is already a crime. When a young homosexual student, Matthew Shepard, was murdered in Wyoming, in October 1998, there was a great outcry for more "hate crime" legislation -- and political demonstrations which, of course, only influence politicians, not murderers -- but since such a murder in Wyoming was already a capital offense, it is not clear what kind of added punishment a hate crime law would add to the sentences of the perpetrators. Many in favor of vast "hate crime" legislation are themselves opposed to the death penalty, and they certainly would never consider adding, for instance, torture to any other kind of capital or prison sentence. We might remember that the more severe forms of capital punishment in England used to involve severing the genitals and slow disembowelment. Would that suit the crime of the murderers of Matthew Shepard? Inquiring minds want to know.

The distortion this introduces into public discourse is evident in the continuing news coverage given to the Shepard case (plays and movies have even been produced about it), while the September 1999 bondage rape and murder of 13-year-old Jesse Dirkhising by two homosexual men in Arkansas has received virtually no attention in the national media, except for conservative commentators. Just as the Shepard case was promoted as evidence of such pervasive "homophobia" as to require federal legislation, those persuaded of Biblical morality could easily offer the Dirkhising case as evidence of pervasive crime by homosexuals. Neither view, of course, is true or proper. Local murders do not appear in the national media unless the media think that some national issue is involved. The Shepard case receives national attention, but not the Dirkhising case, because the national press accepts the importance and the political agenda of federal "hate crime" legislation, while not acknowledging the importance of conservative objections to homosexual practices. This is a political bias. The conservative agenda, however misguided, is just as newsworthy as the leftist one that promotes the category of "hate crimes" involving homosexuals. Either both or neither should receive attention in honest news coverage. The disturbing truth is that the Dirkhising case largely has received no coverage because of the national media bias that facts that might reflect negatively on homosexuals should be, not just under-reported, but actually suppressed.

The truth is that in much political and academic thinking "hate crimes" are not really moral offenses at all, which is why few advocates are ever troubled by the status of homosexuality in Biblical morality. Instead, the advocates of hate crime legislation almost always see these as political crimes, not moral crimes. Political crimes do not call for just retribution, but for punishments that are seen as instruments of social engineering and political suppression, meaning that any punishment sufficient to the end is justified. This dimension is also evident in feminism, which itself sees crimes against women as political crimes -- since, for establishment feminism, everything is political. Thus, even a Republican Congress passed the bizarre "Violence Against Women Act" on the principle that crimes against women were federal "civil rights" offenses. Similarly, feminism thinks of crimes against women as themselves "hate crimes," meaning that what is called "hate" is not really an emotion or a feeling at all -- not all battering husbands, muggers, or even rapists, necessarily hate women -- but a politically incorrect "consciousness," calling for the full weight of federal civil rights authority -- or for political demonstrations, the kinds of things ignored by rapists but noticed by legislators. "Hate" becomes merely a codeword for those violating a certain political program. Thus, the popular theory of hate crimes is no longer even an example of possible judicialism moralism, but just a case of a larger political moralism; and as such, it is not surprising that crimes against homosexuals are not seen as problematic, but instead as obvious, candidates for the "hate crime" category.

Examples

The potential for misuse of the "hate crime" category has become evident in several recent cases. In one of them, an Idaho man, Lonny Rae, was charged with "malicious harassment," a felony, for using the "N" word. This was after an October 2001 football game between local high schools. The fans of the school that lost became angry at the referees, as losing fans often do. Mr. Rae's wife, Kim, was at the game as a freelance reporter and photographer. Because of the possible controversy about the referees, she took pictures of the referees to go with the story. The referees didn't like that and asked her to stop. One of them, who happened to be black, grabbed her camera and tried to yank it away from her. There was a strap from the camera around her neck, so the camera didn't come away, but the strap left some burns and bruises on her neck. When Mr. Rae was informed about this, he went down to where the referees were going into the locker room and began shouting at the black referee in question, liberally using the "N" word. Since arguably an assault had occurred on his wife, his anger is understandable, even if his choice of vocabulary is less so. There was never physical contact between the two men.

Nevertheless, although no charges were filed for assault against the referee, Mr. Rae ended up charged under the Idaho "malicious harassment" hate crime law, which carries a maximum penalty of five years in prison. Since nothing had happened between the two men except Mr. Rae's speech, the only way such an application of this law, which now has nothing to do with aggravating factors in some independently defined unlawful act, could pass muster as not violating the First Amendment is if it fit in under the Supreme Court's "fighting words" exception. With the provocation of the assault on his wife, however, there is a serious mitigating factor about whatever Mr. Rae might have done while angry. The situation was one in which the aggravation (an actual assault) had already occurred. It is therefore fortunate that nothing worse than angry words were involved. The niceties of First Amendment jurisprudence, however, do not seem to have been of concern to the prosecutors, the judge, or the jury. The use of the "bad word" was obviously the offense, all by itself, regardless of the circumstances. In February 2002 the jury, in fact, found Mr. Rae innocent of the "malicious harassment" charge. The judge, however, had suggested that a lesser charge of which he might be guilty could be "misdemeanor assault"; and the jury found Mr. Rae guilty of this. The judge sentenced him to seven days in jail, although jail time for a first such offense is rare. The judge evidently regarded the matter as sufficiently serious to warrant it. So now using a "bad" word is equivalent to an assault -- which is no less than what "critical race theory" legal scholars, like Mari J. Matsuda (Words That Wound: Critical Race Theory, Assaultive Speech, and the First Amendment, 1993), have seriously proposed.

What is serious is the fact of an assault on free speech and the attendant decriminalization of a physical assault. If Mr. Rae is someone who goes around gratuitously shouting the "N" word at black people, then "harassment" is a description that comes to mind. This situation was nothing of the sort, and the actions of the authorities and the court in penalizing the speech and ignoring the prior physical assault betrays a judgment that political crimes are important while mere violent crimes are not. This, indeed, is the tendency of a politicized jurisprudence slipping over into judicial moralism. Mr. Rae's speech betrayed him to be the sort of person who is intrinsically in the wrong, just because of his attitude, regardless of the nature of the events in question. As George Orwell would have said, he is not on "our" side and so is deserving of punishment as a political criminal.

An even worse case is that of Janice Barton of Michigan, who was overheard in August 1998 using the word "spic" in a private comment to her mother, about a group of people speaking Spanish leaving a restaurant near them. In that group was an off-duty deputy sheriff, who heard the comment and wrote down Barton's license plate number. Two weeks later Barton was arrested for "disorderly conduct," later "insulting conduct," and finally a "hate crime." In this case we have a crime consisting of no more than a bad word, and not even one directed at anyone thus characterized. Barton was actually convicted, despite Supreme Court rulings that the only exception to the First Amendment in such a case would be a use of "fighting words" likely to provoke a "breach of the peace." In November 2002 her conviction was reversed by an appeals court, on the principle that this was "conduct she could not reasonably have known was criminal." Usually, courts hold that "ignorance of the law is no excuse"; but in this case ignorance of the law seems to have been the problem with the deputy sheriff, the prosecutors, the judge, the jury, and the appeals court. What it looks like is that the appeals court knew that the conviction was going to be reversed eventually, and so they wanted a pretext to avoid the embarrassment of the Michigan "hate crime" law, if it allowed this conviction, itself being struck down.

In all cases like these, it becomes more apparent that the tendency of "progressive" legislation is a totalitarian hostility to free speech and "politically incorrect" belief, a program that did not die with Communism in 1991 but lives on in the political Left of American universities, law schools, and trendy opinion. The consequences of this are already pervasive in distorted civil rights law.

On 27 April 2011, the BBC reports, "Isle of Wight musician's 'racist' arrest over song":

A musician was arrested after a performance of the 1970s song Kung Fu Fighting at an Isle of Wight bar sparked an alleged racism row with a passer-by.

Simon Ledger, 34, of Shanklin, said he was playing the Carl Douglas hit at the Driftwood bar, Sandown, on Sunday when the man of Chinese origin took offence.

Police said the passer-by claimed he was then "subjected to racial abuse".

Mr Ledger was bailed by police and is expected to be questioned later.

Police said the 32-year-old man was walking past the bar at about 1745 BST when the incident took place.

He contacted officers to make a complaint on the same evening.

Keyboardist Mr Ledger said he was later called and was arrested on suspicion of causing harassment, alarm or distress.

I am perfectly willing to consider the performance of a 1970's Disco song a criminal offense. It would certainly produce "alarm and distress" in me. We see, however, how far free speech has been replaced with thought control in Britain. If Mr. Ledger, perhaps, was gratuitously shouting slurs or insults at the passerby, there may be more to this story. But the prima facie impression it leaves is that Kung Fu Fighting now violates the political (and legal) correctness of racial sensitivity.

In December 2019, Adolfo Martinez of Ames, Iowa, was sentenced to 16 years in prison for stealing and burning the rainbow "gay rights" flag of the Ames United Church of Christ. Many "progressive" churches fly these flags to show that homosexuals, and other "transnormative" people, are welcome in the church. Whether the church means that it does not judge homosexuality (etc.) wrong, and accepts the lifestyle and preferences, or if it simply welcomes all sinners, in the hope that they might eventually accept the traditional moral teaching of the church, is not always clear. Usually, it seems to signify an acceptance of things that Biblical morality would otherwise condemn.

In any case, Martinez was convicted of "third-degree arson in violation of individual rights -- hate crime, third-degree harassment," and "reckless use of fire, as a habitual offender." The "habitual offender" exhancement meant Iowa's "three strikes" law, where a third felony earns a long prison sentence, like the 16 years Martinez was given.

There are certainly some crimes here, namely stealing the flag and burning it, which, not being his property, could count as arson, or at least the "reckless use of fire." Martinez had not previously been a violent offender, and the new crimes in question involved no harm to anyone. New York State is now releasing such people on their own recognizance. The long sentence was the result of only the "hate crime" enhancement, making the conviction a felony.

However, this may be an excellent example of the misuse of "hate crime" laws. The pastor of the Church said of the conviction that, "this man committed a crime and it was crime born of bigotry and hatred." However, burning an American flag has been ruled constitutionally protected political speech. Burning a "gay rights" flag by the same token, to express a moral or political opinion, is also going to be constitutionally protected speech. The mere condemnation of homosexuality cannot be dismissed by the pastor as "bigotry" or even "hate," which perhaps tells us where the pastor is coming from, politically, since he must thereby condemn many of his religious colleagues (although perhaps not in the United Church of Christ) as bigoted and hateful.

While there may be aggrevating factors in theft or arson, protected political expression cannot qualify as such. In the same way, it is not clear how the crime can be judged "third-degree arson in violation of individual rights," when the only "rights" being violated are the property rights of the owner of the flag. But obviously, the judgment here is that burning the flag violates the "rights" of homosexuals (etc.) not to be... what? judged? condemned?

Also, whether there is "harassment" involved here is a good question. Martinez did nothing at the church beyond running off with the flag. How did this "harass" the church or anyone in it? On the other hand, Martinez burned the flag in front of the "Dangerous Curves Gentleman's Club." This might be construed as harassing the club. And if it was a gay club, the harassment might be construed as harassing gay people. However, "Dangerous Curves" is a conventional stripper joint; and if Martinez knew that, he may have been only making a statement -- a Constitutionally protected political statement -- that strip clubs are immoral. Or he may have been confused.

Thus, the motivation for the conviction and sentence here looks like something I have noted in previous examples, that the "crime" involved is really saying or expressing things that are out of favor with the cultural elite and the Ruling Class. "Gay rights" in their terms include the right to force the moral acceptance of homosexuality on others and be free, not of violence, bullying, or harassment, but simply from moral judgment (unless it's by Muslims). It is not clear from this case whether, even if Mr. Martinez had owned the flag himself, it would not still be a hate crime.

Secular Condemnations of Homosexuality

The Polynomic Theory of Value

The Fallacies of Moralism and Moral Aestheticism

Ethics

Value Theory

Home Page

Copyright (c) 1996, 1997, 1998, 1999, 2002, 2003, 2005, 2006, 2010, 2011, 2012, 2014, 2015, 2017, 2020, 2021, 2022, 2023, 2024 Kelley L. Ross, Ph.D. All Rights Reserved

Morality, Justice, and Judicial Moralism; Note 1;
Belief, Will, and Evidence

ἄρα ἡ πίστις ἐξ ἀκοῆς, ἡ ἀκοὴ διὰ ῥήματος Θεοῦ.
ergo fides ex auditu auditus autem per verbum Christi.
So then faith cometh by hearing, and hearing by the word of God.

St. Paul, Romans 10:17; see discussion of "word."


[1:22] For the Jews require a sign [σημεῖον], and the Greeks seek after wisdom [σοφίαν]: [1:23] But we preach Christ crucified, unto the Jews a scandal [σκάνδαλον], and unto the Greeks folly [μωρίαν]; [1:24] But unto them which are called [κλητοῖς], both Jews and Greeks, Christ is the power [δύναμιν] of God and the wisdom of God. [1:25] Because the folly [μωρόν] of God is wiser [σοφώτερον] than men; and the weakness [ἀσθενὲς] of God is stronger [ἰσχυρότερον] than men.

1 Corinthians 1:22-25, cases of original nouns preserved.


[5] καὶ αὐτὸ τοῦτο δὲ σπουδὴν πᾶσαν παρεισενέγκαντες ἐπιχορηγήσατε ἐν τῇ πίστει ὑμῶν τὴν ἀρετήν, ἐν δὲ τῇ ἀρετῇ τὴν γνῶσιν, [6] ἐν δὲ τῇ γνώσει τὴν ἐγκράτειαν, ἐν δὲ τῇ ἐγκρατείᾳ τὴν ὑπομονήν, ἐν δὲ τῇ ὑπομονῇ τὴν εὐσέβειαν, [7] ἐν δὲ τῇ εὐσεβείᾳ τὴν φιλαδελφίαν, ἐν δὲ τῇ φιλαδελφίᾳ τὴν ἀγάπην.

[5] Vos autem curam omnem subinferentes, ministrate in fide vestra virtutem, in virtute autem scientiam, [6] in scientia autem abstinentiam, in abstinentia autem patientiam, in patientia autem pietatem, [7] in pietate autem amorem fraternitatis, in amore autem fraternitatis caritatem.

[5] And beside this, having brought in all diligence, supply also to your faith [πίστις] virtue [ἀρετή]; and to virtue knowledge [γνῶσις]; [6] And to knowledge self-control [ἐγκράτεια]; and to self-control patience [ὑπομονή]; and to patience piety [εὐσέβεια]; [7] And to piety brotherly love [φιλαδελφία]; and to brotherly love divine love [ἀγάπη].

2 Peter 1:5-7, cf. σέβας, "reverential awe, object of awe, holiness, majesty," εὐσεβής, "pious, religious; holy, hallowed, sacred."


ὁ ἄναξ οὗ τὸ μαντεῖόν ἐστι τὸ ἐν Δελφοῖς
οὔτε λέγει οὔτε κρύπτει ἀλλὰ σημαίνει.

The lord whose oracle is in Delphi
neither speaks nor conceals but gives a sign.

Heraclitus of Ephesus, quoted by Plutarch, De Pythiae oraculis 21, 404 E, The Presocratic Philosophers, G.S. Kirk & J.E. Raven, Cambridge, 1964, p.211

While we have seen Jefferson say that belief is not a matter of will, not everyone agrees with this. Some think that beliefs are adopted by choice. And it is not uncommon, starting with "The Will to Believe" by William James, that the choice of religious belief -- -- in particular, may establish a paradigm of will. In Buddhist terms, this would be a doctrine of , Japanese jiriki, "self-power." However, in Buddhism, the issue is not belief or choice, but practice. Practice leads to enlightenment, either through the accumulation of merit or more directly.

Belief is fundamentally not a matter of choice because even if you "choose" to believe something, this is irrelevant to whether it is true or not. This is obvious if you are coerced into confessing belief, where questions about truth may be regarded as hostile and wicked. Similarly, if the determinist says that beliefs are caused, this also leaves questions of truth aside. That turned up in the debate beween C.S. Lewis and Elizabeth Anscombe about determinism, where Anscombe didn't seem to understand Lewis's argument and thought that issues of justification refuted, rather than supported, Lewis. In the same way, people may believe something for reasons that seem cogent to them but that are actually irrelevant to truth. Confessing belief may gain social acceptance, even without coercion, despite the irrelevance of social approval to truth. Many people believe things just because it makes them "feel good."

In terms of evidence, there are degrees of evidentiary support. Philosophers now love Bayes' Theorem, P(A|B) = P(A)*P(B|A)/P(B), which allows probability to rise with increased evidence. This may blur questions of choice. In considering something one believes, or perhaps even something about which one is uncertain, evidence may accumulate one way or another to the point where a judgment can be made about its adequacy for justification. The threshold for that varies with one's standards of evidence, one's inclination to scepticism, one's initial attitude towards the issues, and other factors, all of of which may fade in and out in terms of actual relevance to truth. How probable should something be before it is accepted? When a judgment is then made, it may look like a choice. At times it may really be a choice, but then the result is less a belief than a hypothesis, whose foundation is tentative. Indeed, no amount of probability, short of 100%, makes for certainty. Clinging to a belief against which the tide of evidence has turned tends to betray reasons for belief that are irrelevant to truth. Indeed, some reasons for belief may be reasonable, even if they are, strickly speaking, irrelevant to truth.

In Existentialism, all matters of value, whose cognitive foundations are obscure and disputed, are established by choice, albeit if only for the individual making the choices. In Kierkegaard, religious belief may be regarded as choice that amounts to a "leap of faith" which is entirely irrational and without any evidentiary foundation. That is the essence of Existentialism. In an absurd world, the proper response may be to do the most absurd thing, which to the modern bien pensant, generally a materialist and an atheist, would be religious faith. Yet the views of modern nihilists tend to go in darker directions.

However, faith as choice is not really what we see in the history of religion, Tertulian not withstanding. And if religious faith were entirely an act of irrational, i.e. arbitrary, will, how does one distinguish between religions? Once religions are perceived as different, then their differences quickly become matters of discrimination between them. St. Thomas Aquinas did not write the Summa Contra Gentiles in order to say that Christianity was superior to Judaism or Islam because of an irrational choice.

St. Thomas wanted to say that Christianity was displaying a rational moral superiority over the other religions, which would then provide a clue to its mysteries that might transcend reason. But many people, who consider different religions in their quest for the answers to life, do not think of it in terms of rational discrimination. They are looking for a feeling or, perhaps more to the point, a Sign -- Greek σημεῖον, sēmeîon (plural σημεῖα, sēmeîa); Arabic , ʾāyah, "sign, token, mark; miracle, wonder, marvel" (plural , ʾāyāt), , ʾāyah maimūnah, "auspicious sign"; Sanskrit, , lakṣaṇa, "mark, token, sign," , sulakṣaṇa, "having auspicious marks"; Chinese , Japanese zuisō, "auspicious signs," "good omen." Jesus did "many signs," πολλὰ σημεῖα, , ʾāyāt kaθīrah (in Arabic translation). The M. Night Shyamalan movie Signs [2002] features an ex-priest, played by Mel Gibson, who had lost his faith because of his wife's death, but who regains it because his wife's last words apparently contained accurate prophecies, i.e. "Signs," whose realization saves Gibson and his family.

On the road to Damascus, St. Paul was struck blind and heard the voice of Jesus. That's a pretty substantial sign. A fictional example, but a nice one, is the conversion experience of Samuel L. Jackson in the movie Pulp Fiction [1994]. Jackson claimed to have seen a miracle, but whether it was really a miracle or not, what made the difference was that he felt "the touch of God." After that, it is not a matter of will or choice.

But we don't always need fiction. As recounted by the Israeli National News:

[Jon] Voight tells Tucker Carlson that, during a tough period, he cried out 'It's so hard,' and heard a voice reply, 'It's supposed to be hard.' [July 15, 2021]

At a low time in his life, when he was feeling a lot of despair, this enabled Voight to get cleaned up and back on track -- with faith.

It is possible to accept faith as a matter of will. But the Existentialist will, based on nothing else, is going to be exhausting. It can crack at any moment. People who are raised in faith may find comfort in it without any act of will. If they lose their faith, however, they may have difficulty getting it back. It may seem absurd to them that one would just "decide" to have it back, and the result may be bitterness and a sense of disilluioned betrayal (is this characteristic of lapsed Catholics?). If something happened that shook their faith, something should happen to bring it back. They need "the touch of God" or, at least, a Sign.

Thus, while religious belief might be seen, and has been, as a matter of will, what seems to be involved in it in personal and historical experience is more complex. It is not a matter of reason and rational evidence; but there are other kinds of evidence. The rationalist is likely to dismiss "signs" as no evidence at all. But then the rationalist who, in a meaningless world, becomes a nihilist, will accept no evidence for anything.

At 1 Corinthians 1:22, Paul considers the alternatives of "wisdom" for the Greeks and "signs" for the Jews. He implies that the Christian needs neither; but, while he does not offer "choice" as the alternative, he obviously has benefited himself from a "sign" to warrant his own conversion. He does identify Christians as those who are "called," κλητοί; but then we don't hear how that ordinarily happens. So the issues there have not been clearly distinguished, even while the rationalist, who lapses into nihilism in the absence of "wisdom," never gives the slightest attention to the meaning of a "sign." Yet the fear and complaint of the Pharisees against Jesus was that, οὗτος ὁ ἄνθρωπος πολλὰ ποιεῖ σημεῖα, "This man does many signs" [John 11:47]. One clue may be Romans 10:17, as quoted in the epigraph. But if "faith comes by hearing," this places a premium on how the "Word of God," ῥῆμα Θεοῦ, is delivered. Not just any fire and brimstone will do. But then the "Word of God" can just mean the text of the Gospel.

πολλοὶ γὰρ εἰσιν κλητοί, ὀλίγοι δὲ ἐκλεκτοί.
Multi autem sunt vocati, pauci vero electi.
For many are called, but few are chosen.

Matthew 22:14

However, being "called," κλητοί, according to Matthew 22:14, does not seem to be enough. In this mysterious verse, we are brought to a choice, but it is not our choice. Instead the choice lies elsewhere, so that we may become "chosen," ἐκλεκτοί. Calvinists liked this a lot; and we see them using the term from Latin, electi, the "Elect," who are then predestined for that status. That is not generally popular in Christianity.

The actual choice, in much traditional theology, perhaps beginning with St. Augustine, is made by God; and it is manfest as his "grace," χάρις. How we are worthy or prepared to receive God's grace is the next question. In Buddhist terms, this would be a doctrine of , Japanese tariki, "other-power," the most characteristic thing of Jōdo Buddhism, where birth in the Pure Land of the Buddha Amitābha means relying alone, by faith, on the power of his Vow.

An early Jesuit missionary in Japan, Alessandro Valignano, said that such a doctrine, of salvation by "faith alone," was the same heresy that the devil had taught to Martin Luther. However, even Catholic doctrine allows that salvation can be achieved by faith alone in articulo mortis, even at the moment of death. But we do get a characteristic practice in Jōdo, which is chanting the Nembutsu mantra:  , Japanese Namu Amida Butsu. You will choose, to be sure, to chant the Nembutsu; but, certainly for Shinran (1174-1268), this signifies but does not cause faith. Otherwise, the tradition is that you should be sure to chant ten Nembutsu just before death.

Faith, Works, and Knowledge

Return to Text

Morality, Justice, and Judicial Moralism; Note 2

Schopenhauer says:

Thus the law and its fulfilment, namely punishment, are directed essentially to the future, not to the past. This distinguishes punishment from revenge, for revenge is motivated simply by what has happened, and hence by the past as such. All retaliation for wrong by inflicting a pain without any object for the future is revenge, and can have no other purpose than consolation for the suffering one has endured by the sight of the sufferng one has caused in another. Such a thing is wickedness and cruelty, and cannot be ethically justified. Wrong inflicted on me by someone does not in any way entitle me to inflict wrong on him. Retaliation of evil for evil without any further purpose cannot be justified, either morally or otherwise, by any ground of reason, and the jus talionis, set up as an independent, ultimate principle of the right to punish, is meaningless. Therefore, Kant's theory of punishment as mere requital for requital's sake is a thoroughly groundless and perverse view. [The World as Will and Representation, Volume I, §62, p.348 [Dover Publications, 1966, E.F.J. Payne translation, boldface added]

Therefore, Schopenhauer believes that deterrence is the only purpose of punishment that is reasonable and proper.

However, there are circumstances where the dynamic of deterrence in comparison to pure retribution reveals the inadequacy of the former. If the purpose of punishment is deterrence, then clearly the punishment must be sufficient to accomplish that deterrence. This is a different consideration from that of justice alone, where the ancient sense is that the punishment should "fit" the crime, or especially be proportional to the crime. Punishment that is disproportionate to the offense is, as Schopenhauer himself puts it, "wickedness and cruelty." The ancient word for such laws is "draconian."

Edward Gibbon says in an epigraph to this page:

Whenever the offense inspires less horror than the punishment, the rigor of penal law is obliged to give way to the common feelings of mankind.

In most cases that would traditionally be of a criminal nature, there is not much of a problem here. Indeed, in the Code of Hammurabi and in the Bible, the principle of "an eye for an eye, and a tooth for a tooth" provides, not only perfect proportionality, but also what most would think of as fully adequate deterrence. Oddly enough, more of a problem emerges in modern law, much of which is novel and regulatory, despite our general sense that modern law has become more humane and enlightened (since we don't have mutilations, flogging, or drawing and quartering -- at least in Western law). Thus, traditional wrongs are mala in se, "evils in themselves," while the modern state prohibits and criminalizes things that had never been wrongs but that are now regarded as socially or politically undesirable. They are mala prohibita, evils are are simply prohibited, by the power of the State.

Now, since mala prohibita are not natural wrongs and may appear to many people as not very serious, the results of political grandstanding, or positive evils in themselves (such as drug laws that deny pain medication to the sick, or arrest them), we see the dynamic whereby the punishment for them, if it is to really deter, must be magnified. It was not long ago that a person arrested for possession of marijuana in Texas might receive life in prison, while murderers might only get a few years. But this is quite proper, on Schopenhauer's reasoning, if the only possible justification of punishment is deterrence. The punishment must be enough to actually deter. Consequently, Thelma and Louise drove around Texas.

The results, however, are obvious and grotesque injustices, if one's principle is the proportionality of punishment. This reveals that proportionality is a pure principle of retribution and justice, unrelated to deterrence. Schopenhauer has overlooked this. He has also overlooked the deterrent power of revenge, which is evident both on the playground, in gang warfare, and in conditions approaching the "state of nature," such as international relations. If you hurt us, and we hurt you back, perhaps with a punitive magnification, you will be reluctant to try and hurt us again.

What we see in the difference between retribution and deterrence is a typological difference discussed elsewhere. To Kant, the proper motive for moral action is not fear of punishment, but consciousness of duty. Retribution balances wrongs with evils, which is why proportionality is required. This addresses moral duty as something unrelated to consequences. Deterrence converts moral considerations into prudential ones. I will avoid doing wrongs, not because they are wrongs, but because I might get caught and punished. This leaves anyone to reason that the problem there is just avoiding capture and punishment, not avoiding wrong.

Schopenhauer, or anyone else, is free to think of punishment as justified only by deterrence; but such reasoning alone can generate errors, and produce injustices, unless we add the feature of retribution, and proportionality, as purely matters of justice. Also, today, we must consider that regulatory or political prohibitions cannot in general involve punishment more serious than for mala in se. Indeed, they should not be criminal matters at all, unless harms are involved that themselves qualify as mala in se. But, as we see elsewhere on this page (in regard to "strict liablity"), modern jurisprudence, with its dominant positivism, increasingly disregards the most essential features of proper justice.

Of course, if the punishments for violations of a malum prohibitum law are not sufficient to deter the widespread disregard of the law, the legislator, judge, or jury should consider whether this exposes the improper or foolish nature of such legislation. The present dynamic is for politicians to think that they should increase the penalties when their fellow citizens ignore the law. When effected, this constitutes, not justice, but a kind of revenge of the state against those who would defy it. A revenge with an ignoble motive that defies proportionality.

Typology of Motives and Virtues

Return to Text

Morality, Justice, and Judicial Moralism; Note 3:
Teaching Hate

The argument that "hate" is the general problem, and that everything can be fixed by teaching everyone not to hate anyone, is contradicted by the practice of American education, which now teaches a general hatred of the United States and its history and also, quite generally, of white people. Of course, a general hatred of white people is, quite simply, racism, which otherwise is condemned as the most evil of all evils, and the greatest crime of all crimes. Indeed, the educational curriculum of hatred of America consists of condemnations of America for its supposed perpetual and universal racism, which originated in the existence of slavery (which America invented just to oppress Africans), transmuted into racial Segregation, and then continues as the "institutional racism" that condemns racial minorities (except for Chinese, Japanese, Koreans, Vietnamese, people from India, etc.) to perpetual poverty, often just by allowing people to express opinions that are contrary to this narrative.

The origin of this incoherent ideology and practice is intriguing, perhaps even in just psychological terms. "Liberal guilt" is the problem that political "progressives" feel unworthy of their own success and "privileged" status. To expiate the sin of their own success, these people must abase themselves, display repentance, and perform some sort of penance. As in the Christian consciousness of sinfulness, what is essential to this is a deepening of their sense of unworthiness. Thus, "liberal guilt" evolves into self-hatred, for which some sort of equivalent of self-flagellation is no less than what is required.

Behind all of that is a loss of understanding of how people become economically successful. All successful ethnic groups in American history have a record of starting small businesses. The Koreans or people from India running the neighborhood Seven-Eleven is a familiar feature, indeed a stereotype, of modern American life. People from India are also familiar from becoming physicians or running hotels and motels. The result is that Indians as a group have become, according to U.S. Census data, the most successful ethnic group in the United States. Jews might be more successful, but the Census does not track religion. But the Jewish experience is obviously similar. Small businesses leading to professional careers, in law, medicine, academia, etc., is the story of many Jewish families. And, as with Indians and the Chinese, restaurants loom large in Jewish business history.

On the other hand, American Indians are among the poorest of ethnic groups in the United States. But their lack of business experience is conspicuous. New Mexico author Tony Hillerman, voted a Friend of the Navajo Nation, nevertheless explained the lack of Navajo run businesses as the result of Navajo relatives expecting, not jobs from successful businesses, but free things from the inventory and capital of any Navajo business. Which consequently is bankrupted. The alternative is to "act like they don't have any relatives." But, indeed, successful ethnic groups do help their relatives, both by providing jobs and helping them start, in turn, their own businesses. Why that paradigm never developed among the Navajo is a good question.

"Liberal guilt" seems to arise from circumstances different from those of entrepreneurial ethnic groups. The 1950's father who works long hours at the office sustains the life-style of his family, and his large corporation may be willing to hire his children, but starting in the mail-room likely would be much less appealing than the goal of a college education and a professional career path. Dad, indeed, may seem like a drudge, and his own career deeply "unfulfilling." So it became common among Baby Boomers to disparage the life of their parents, often not understanding the connection between the comfort of their homes and childhood with the hard work that sustained it. So hippies ran off to Nature, often didn't even bathe, and before long had to face some of the hard realities of prudence, like skin diseases. But, having not been raised by the side of a cash register, they still may not have understood some of the most basic features of economic life and development. Especially after their college "education," they may end up with no better than a Cargo Cult understanding of economics.

Such people may feel "privileged" in the sense that they are entitled and owed wealth without much understanding of how such a thing is created in the first place and, seeing that they get more than others, they may feel naturally guilty why that should be -- forgetting that their parents or grandparents may have worked like dogs to achieve their success. And since white people, or Europeans, seem to be more successful than others, this guilt can be generalized into a belief that this has not been earned or merited. Perhaps the technology of the Inustrial Revolution had already been created by the Ancient Egyptians and was then stolen from them, perhaps with time machines.

This determination, however, despite ignoring so many things that were never learned or taught, must also ignore some rather obvious contemporary things. The economic success of Japan, South Korea, Taiwan, and at least large parts of India and mainland China, and of immigrants from these countries in the United States, falsifies both "liberal guilt" and "white guilt." How IQ or SAT questions can be "culturally biased" for white people, when the children of Vietnamese or Cambodian refugees do better than white children, is a mystery that must be devoutely ignored. Or how could black immigrants from the West Indies be more successful than native American black people? Is white racism defused by the charm of a Jamaican accent? This seems unlikely. But I'll consider it.

Ignored indeed. The narrative of "white privilege," infused by self-hatred, growing into racial self-hatred, becomes Faith and Dogma, and not anything that can be corrected by mere facts. The ignorance and incoherence of all this cannot be expressed with cogent or even articulate arguments. It is best expressed as rage. I.E. hatred. So it is hatred that must be taught.

The shameful case of Oblerlin College illustrates this nicely. At this most liberal of Liberal Arts colleges, in Oblerlin, Ohio, in 2016 some Oberlin students were caught shoplifting at a local bakery, Gibson's, which had served the College for 134 years. Although obviously guilty, and confessing, the students were defended by radical student organizations at the College, who decided that it was all about racism, i.e. the racism of the (family) bakery. Teachers and Administrators at the College joined in with a virtual Hate Fest against the bakery, which consequently lost business and reputation, and well as enduring threats of violence -- which is something that screaming mobs of protesters tends to imply.

Gibson's sued the College for defamation and related wrongs and won a jury settlement of $11 million. The College refuses to admit guilt and is fighting the verdict. But the actions of the radical students and the support of the College had nothing going except hate. Their complaint against the bakery was fact free, except for the fact that the bakery family was white. And therefore racists and "white supremacists." Now the College claims it was all about free speech. Nonsense. It is not "free speech" to knowingly voice libelous falsehoods, destroying the livelihood of innocent people.

Thus, Oberlin College suffers from its own kind of moral disease, which, ironically, can be diagnosed in the terms of its own ideology. It is consumed by a racist hatred and animus. And this is what it has been teaching students: hate white people. And business -- let's not forget that.

Return to Text